|
-
TRUTH AND ZEN
-
By T. P. Kasulis
- --o0o--
-
-
Truth and Zen
Buddhism it is difficult to imagine a pair of more abstruse. yet
fascinating, topics, Rather than discuss either one of the two, I will
consider them both simultaneously in hopes that, like some schoolboy
magician in a chemistry laboratory, I might mix together two murky,
colored concoctions and thereby effect-abracadabra-a transparent,
clear solution.
-
To begin our
analysis of truth, we need the same general framework. Aristotle
points us in a classical, though still relevant, direction. In an
argument for the validity of the principle of the excluded middle.
Aristotle
makes the well-known definition: To say of what is that it is not, or
of what is not that it is, is false, while to say of what is that it
is, and of what is not that it is not, is true Metaphysics, (1011(b)).
-
This
definition sets down the general principle of correspondence and
captures quite well the man on the street view of truth.
Aristotle,
however, is not the man on the street (he may be peripatetic, but he
is hardly pedestrian); if we wish a clearer picture of
Aristotle's
view of truth, we must look more closely at what he says in other
parts of his writings. In this regard, it is helpful to see how
Aristotle
defines "false" in the lexiconical section of the Metaphysics
(1024(b)). For Aristotle, there are three kinds of falseness: false as
a thing, false as an account, and false as a person. The second of
this triad obviously relates directly to the preceding definition, but
what of the other two? A thing (pragma) may be false in either of two
ways. First, a false thing is a state of affairs that does not always
pertain, for example, the commensurability of the diagonal of a square
with its sides (which never pertains) and my sitting down (which is
not always the case). Aristotle's point is not very clear here.
Perhaps for a state of affairs to be "true" in his proposed sense, it
must be true in itself without reference to any particular
configuration of reality at a given time. That is, Aristotle may have
in mind states of affairs that can be known to be true on a priori
grounds. Fortunately, for our purposes, the other sense of the
falsehood of things is more important so we will not dwell on this
point any further. The second way for a thing to be false is for it to
appear to us to be other than what it is really. Thus, Aristotle gives
the examples of dreams and sketches, things which actually exist (as
dreams and sketches) but which lead us to believe they have an
existence of a different sort. Thus, dreams are confused with sense
perceptions and our perception of the sketch is confused with a
perception of the thing the sketch portrays. The important point here
is that the confusion is based in the thing's appearance, not in our
evaluation. Hence, we are here speaking of false things, not false
judgments, according to Aristotle. What of falsehood insofar as it
applies to persons? A false person is one who likes to give false
accounts for their own sake and who is skilled in convincing others of
their truth Persons.
Aristotle
comments, are false in one of the ways that things are false, namely,
they "produce a false appearance." In one sense, the truth of persons
amounts to truth-telling or honesty, but again we would do well to
view this in the larger Aristotelian context. For
Aristotle, a
person who knows true accounts. But delights in misleading others, is
one who corrupts his own character. That is false persons present not
only accounts, but also themselves, falsely. Behind this standpoint is
the classical position that what one knows cannot be separated from
what one is: to distort willfully the truth of one's own knowledge is
to distort the truth of one's own personhood.
-
In short,
even though it may be correct that
Aristotle
is a straightforward correspondence theorist in his formal definition
of truth, it is equally clear that
Aristotle
wants to say more about truth than can be encompassed by that
definition. Why? Why is Aristotle not satisfied with just the truth of
accounts? Is there some intimate and profound relationship among the
three truths? I believe there is.
Aristotle
is not only interested in the definition of truth; he is also
interested in the acquisition of truth. In contemporary philosophy as
well, we are familiar with the distinction between theories of the
meaning of truth and theories of the means to acquiring truth, so
Aristotle's concerns are not really foreign to us. We should not be
too hasty with this comparison, however. In our framework, we may say
the question of the meaning of truth is a metaphysical one, but the
issue of the means to truth falls in the domain of epistemology.
Aristotle differs in that his concern for the acquisition of truth is,
at least in part, metaphysical as well as epistemological. That is to
say, as a metaphysicia... Aristotle feels compelled not only to define
truth, but also to explain metaphysically how it is that the
acquisition of truth is possible. In this respect, for true accounts
to be possible, there must be true things and true persons a well. If
things did not generally appear as they are and if persons were not
generally honest with themselves and with others, there would be no
touchstone for us in making judgments about what is. In other words, a
stipulation for the correspondence between what-is-said and what-is is
that what-is show itself as what-it-is and that what-is-said be a
genuine expression of what-one-experiences. This nis the fundamentally
metaphysical connection among
Aristotle's
three truths.
-
This
Aristotelian account of the metaphysics of truth will be a useful
Guide in our discussion of the
Ch'an
and Zen tradition. Let us begin with the Platform Suutra of the Sixth
Patriarch, one of the first major works to be distinctively
Ch'an
in orientation. Its author, Hui-neng, lived in the seventh and eighth
centuries and supposedly founded the eventually dominant southern
school
of Ch'an Buddhism. If we take "truth" to correspond roughly to the
Chinese character chen(3), Hui-neng speaks of truth most often in
terms of the "truly-so" (chen-ju(b)). the sinification of the Sanskrit
term tathataa. In the Platform Suutra this tathataa is understood to
be the essence or substance of thought; thoughts are taken to be the
functioning of tathataa (ch. 17). In this way, tathataa becomes
equivalent to the primal or original nature. that to which one awakens
when one sees into one's own mind (ch. 31). In short, Hui-neng's
language is reminiscent of the basic Fa-hsiang(c) or Yogaacaara
position. there is an original nature (pen-hsing(d) ) that, when left
unpolluted in no-thinking (wu-nien(e)), becomes the functioning truly
so. Thus. it seems that Hui-neng is saying that at the base of the
mind, we find the basis of truth. We must be cautious with this
interpretation, however. Various Yogaacaara texts, especially the
La^nkaavataara Suutra, were very influential in the early development
of Ch'an Buddhism and Hui-neng's choice of words reflects this
connection. Therefore, even though Hui-neng may use terminology that
correlates. In some ways, with Yogaacaara's idealistic view of
reality, this may be more a matter of historical accident than deep
philosophical commitment.
-
The question
that now arises is whether Hui-neng's view is in any way similar to
any aspect of Aristotle's threefold view of truth. In certain
respects. Hui-neng's truly-so and Aristotle's truth of things serve a
similar metaphysical function. That is, in both cases, the nature of
reality appears as it is. In fact, Hui-neng is more radical in this
regard in that Aristotle recognizes the existence of at least some
false things, but the Platform Suutra's truly so is apparently all
inclusive. Despite this difference, Aristotle and Hui-neng agree on
one crucial issue: the major cause of falsehood is our mistaken
interpretations of what appears. The world is not fundamentally
illusory: it is our own delusions that prevent us from seeing the way
things are.
-
But what of
Hui-neng's idealistic strain? After all, the Platform Suutra implies
that we come to know the truth when we see into our own minds.
Certainly, this seems to be a direct violation of the Aristotelian
notion of correspondence. But does it have to be? Let us consider
Thomas
version of Aristotelian correspondence (Summa
Theologica, Part I, Q. 21, Art. 2): Truth consists in the equation of
mind and thing.... Now the mind. that is the cause of the thing, is
related to it as its rule and measure: where as the converse is the
case with the mind, that receives its knowledge from things. When
therefore things are the measure and rule of mind, truth consists in
the equation of the mind to the thing.... But when the mind is the
rule or measure of things, truth consists in the equation of the thing
to the mind: just as the work of the artist is said to to true, when
it is in accordance with his art.
-
Thomas
explicitly states here that the correspondence between the mind and
what-is can occur in either of two ways: either the what is can be the
standard to which the mind conforms or vice versa. We will have the
opportunity to discuss the second alternative at a later point. For
now, let us focus on the first, the one we have been discussing thus
far: the mind is the receptor of percepts and adjusts itself to what
the senses report. In light of our concern about Hui-neng's idealism,
we should take note of the fact that
Thomas
sees this correspondence as an internal relationship within
consciousness, that is the correspondence is really between thoughts
and sense experiences, not thoughts and things. This leads
Thomas
to the striking statement: "Truth resides only in the intellect" (S.
T. part I, Q. 16, Art. 1) . Later (in Art. 3).
Thomas
quotes
Aristotle's
De
Anima
(431(b)) for support: "The soul is in a way all existing things; for
existing things are either sensible or thinkable...." There is a
potential equivocation here: when Aristotle and Thomas consider the
definition of truth, they speak of the correspondence between mind and
things; but when they consider the practical test for truth, the
correspondence seems to be between two mental constituents:
interpretation and phenomena. Here, though,
Aristotle's
three truths resolve the difficulty. Because of the metaphysical
stipulation that most things are true, what-is is generally what
appears. Thus, we need worry about the discrepancy between phenomena
and things only in those rare cases wherein a false thing appears.
Here previous experience and habit play an important role: we learn
not to trust dreams and sketches, for example, on face value. In the
case of Hui-neng, as we have seen, the theory does not admit the
possibility of false things; everything is essentially tathataa.
Therefore, in practice, things and phenomena coalesce. In this
restricted sense, then, Hui-neng's theory, as a theory about the
acquisition of truth, is not necessarily any more idealistic than
Aristotle's or Thomas'.
-
Still,
philosophically speaking, Hui-neng's view of truth is not as
sophisticated as that of Aristotle and Thomas. Most importantly,
Hui-neng does not develop any explicit idea of the truth of persons.
This is an important omission in the following respect: if things are
intrinsically true, how is it that delusions arise? Obviously, this
must be the result of some deficiency in the person, but the Platform
Suutra does not develop this idea in any detail. This is not to say
that Hui-neng did not recognize the importance of the person in his
training methods; the interpersonal encounter between master and
disciple was as much a part of Ch'an or Zen training then as it is
now. The point, however, is that the written account in the Platform
Suutra is more mechanistic than personalistic. It is understandable
that the following famous koan would be attributed to Hui-neng:
"Without any consideration of good or evil, right now. What is your
original face before your parents were born?" It is consistent with
Hui-neng's position to emphasize such a fundamental amoral reality
which (pon enlightenment) comes to function as the mind of the person.
Still, an emphasis on the truth of the person, rather than on the
ontology of the truly-so, would seem to be a more useful account for
Ch'an practice. Lin-chi apparently agrees. About one and a half
centuries after Hui-neng, Lin-chi founded the southern Ch'an line of
transmission named after him. In the Lin-chi Records the treatment of
truth is headed in the direction we have already anticipated. Rather
than the truly-so, Lin-chi emphasizes the "true person" (chen-jen(t));
rather than Hui-neng's no-thinking, Lin-chi speaks of "no position"
(wu-wei(u) ) . Putting these together, we find in the third chapter
Lin-chi's famous reference to the "true person of no position." This
term played a central role in Lin-chi's training techniques, and he
often demanded of his disciples that they make manifest this true
nature of the personality. In a sense, Lin-chi sees a fundamental
connection between Hui-neng's "original nature" and "original face;"
that is, Lin-chi makes it explicit that the truly-so is manifested in
the activity of the true person. The truth is based as much in
theperson as it is in the tathataa. The roots of Lin-chi's idea may be
in chapter 6 of the Chuang-tzu: "There must first be a true person
before there can be true knowledge." The "true person" is one of
Chuang-tzu's common designations for the sage who acts spontaneously,
responsively, and without contrivance. In this respect, we can
understand Hui-neng's "no-thinking" as a state of responsive awareness
in which one is not self-consciously putting one's experience into
static con-ceptual frameworks. In any case, Lin-chi expressly states
that the true person represents the spontaneous functioning at the
basis of all human activity (3; ch. 3) and the mode in which intention
and act are inseparable (yao-hsing-chi-hsing; yao-tso-chi-tso(h), 11d,
ch. 10).
-
In short,
Lin-chi recognizes that for correspondence to take place, there must
be not only the world and the mind, but also the activity of
corresponding itself; this activity is the functioning of the true
person. "Moreover, make yourself master of your situation; wherever
you stand is truth" (13a; ch. 12). What is Lin-chi's position on
idealism? Although he does say that there is no dharma external to the
person, he points out (27; ch. 18) that this should not be taken to
mean that the dharma is accessible through inactive, introspective
contemplation. The dharma is not located in any single place; it is
not something toward which one takes a stand. The true person has no
status or position; wherever that person stands is truth. I take this
to be a response to the idealistic reading of Hui-neng. Lin-chi wants
it to be clear that the ideal is not to transcend the external world
and withdraw into the mind; rather, the ideal is to find the truly-so,
to discover the true person, in one's spontaneous and responsive
activity within the world.
-
This
discussion of the activity of the true person returns us to a
fore-mentioned, but as yet unanalyzed, point in
Thomas'
view of truth. We noted above that
Thomas
discussed two ways in which the correspondence between mind and things
can occur: either the mind can conform to things or things can conform
to the mind. it is this latter possibility that concerns us now.
Thomas'
example of the artwork is a fruitful one. Here we have the case that
the mind becomes the rule for the term of the thing and if the artwork
fulfills the intent of the mind, we can say there is a correspondence
between the intellect and what-is. Hence, Thomas maintains that it is
appropriate to speak of truth in artistic creativity. (incidentally,
this medieval view of truth in art has had its impact even on
contemporary theories of aesthetics; see, for example, Albert
Hofstadter's discussion of the "truth of things" in his Truth and
Art.) The question that now faces us is this: Lin-chi has maintained
that the truth of things can be manifested in the activity of the true
person, but would he also say that the truth of things can be created
by some activity of the true person? No, to make truth even partially
dependent for its existence on the person would be to deny that all
things in themselves are tathataa. Here we have an important
divergence between the Ch'an Buddhists and part of the Western
tradition. We will return to this point later.
-
A second
point of divergence is that
Aristotle
and
Thomas
hold that the truth of persons is of concern to ethics as well as to
metaphysics and epistemology. That is, truth insofar as it applies to
persons is a virtue. In the Nicomachean Ethics (1127(a)), for example,
Aristotle says that truth is the mean between boastfulness and false
modesty.
-
Thomas adds
to the list of vices opposing truth two more: lying and dissimulation
or hypocrisy (S. T. Part II-II, Q. 110-113). The
Ch'an
tradition does not discuss truth as a virtue. There are various
reasons for this: Ch'an Buddhism wanted to distinguish itself from the
Confucianist emphasis on virtues and the Hiinayaanist orientation
toward the precepts, for example. The true person for Lin-chi (and for
Chuang-tzu, in fact) acts naturally and is not consciously trying to
live up to some ideal.
-
Hence,
explicit reference to ethics is avoided. In fairness, however, it
should be noted that there is some common ground beneath the
divergence just noted. One could easily argue that for the classical
philosopher, to display virtue (virtus) is really just actualizing
one's inherent potential to be a man (vir). Taking this tack, it is
much more difficult to distinguish sharply the Zen project of
manifesting one's original face (Buddha-nature, true personhood) from
this classical sense of virtue. Thus, the distinction between the two
traditions may not be as hard and fast as the prima facie evidence
would indicate.
-
The
discussion of truth as virtue does raise another important point,
however. In Aristotle and Thomas, truth-telling is primarily posed in
terms of presenting oneself to others. That is, the true person (one
possessing the virtue, truth) does not mislead others. In Lin-chi,
however, the emphasis is on self-awareness, that is, one who is a true
person does not lie to oneself. Of course, these two orientations are
not mutually exclusive and, in fact, they are ultimately
interdependent. Nevertheless, the difference in emphasis is striking.
As we shall see, the Ch'an and Zen emphasis approaches more the
existentialist sense of authenticity than truth-telling in the
ordinary sense.
-
For a more
holistic account of the Zen position, we will turn now to the writings
of Dogen, a thirteenth-century Japanese Zen master. Dogen is probably
the most systematic and philosophically inclined of all Zen or Ch'an
writers. Thus, although he does not explicitly say much about "truth,"
he does address himself to many of the same issues that have concerned
us here. Even though Dogen is traditionally associated with the
Soto
rather than the Rinzai (Lin-chi) branon of Zen. Dogen did not so
identify himself. For the purposes of this article, he can be seen as
a legitimate heir of Hui-neng and Lin-chi, at least regarding their
view of truth.
-
Even though
Dogen makes scattered references to tathataa, he has his own term for
the truth of things, namely, genjokoan(l), "things' being present as
they are." Hence, like most of his
Ch'an
predecessors, Dogen, in effect, denies that there is illusion; there
are only the delusions we inflict on ourselves. From this standpoint,
even a dream as dream is tathataa; if someone should take it to be
other than it is (as sense experience, for example), the
interpretation, not the thing, is the locus of falsehood. Thus, if we
analyze Dogen's view of interpretation, we will reach the heart of his
view on truth and falsehood.
-
In referring
to enlightenment, it is significant that Dogen generally prefers to
use the term "authentication" (sho(j)) rather than "realization"
satori(k)). While the word "realization" often has the connotation of
being a single incidence of recognition, the term "authentication" may
convey the nuance of a continual verification of the genuineness of
one's interpretation. Dogen does not reject the importance of sudden
insight (he himself had such a peak experience while in China), but it
is the process of continual authentication that best characterizes the
unique character of enlightenment. But how does the enlightened person
test his or her interpretation? Like
Thomas,
Dogen would maintain that there is no extraexperiential touchstone, no
thing-in-itself that can serve as the standard for evaluation. As
Thomas
says, "truth resides only in the intellect," that is, consciousness
must reflect on itself (either intuitively or conceptually) so as to
maintain the correspondence between its interpretative structures and
its sense experiences. Dogen's major work, The Treasury of the Correct
Dharma-eye (Shobogenzo(l) ), is filled with exhortatives that urge his
disciples to examine their own experiences and to authenticate their
understanding of what is. Still, Dogen differs from Thomas in
maintaining that a special mode of reflexive consciousness is needed
for this authenticating process. In his fascicle, "A Talk about
Undertaking the Way" (Bendowa(m)), Dogen writes (p.729):
-
The Buddhas
and Tathaagatas have the wondrous art wu-wei(n): they directly
transmit to each other the wondrous dharma and authenticate perfect
enlightenment. Being passed on directly from Buddha to Buddha, this
(transmission) is without distortion, i.e., jijuyuu sammai(o) itself
is the touchstone.
-
What does
Dogen mean by this jijuyuu sammai? "Sammai" is the Japanese equivalent
to the Sanskrit "samaadhi," a high-level meditative state. "Jijuyuu"
is a difficult term to translate; basically it is the sense of
spiritual well-being derived from Zen practice and utilized in one's
personal affairs. Hence, it is a saintly serenity and joy that one
brings to one's daily life. To understand the relevance of this to
authentication, we must be clear about Dogen's view of Zen practice,
especially zazen(p), "seated meditation."
-
In two
fascicles, "The Principles of Zazen" (Zazengi(q)) and Admonitions
about Zazen" (Zazenshin(r) ) . Dogen utilizes a distinction among
three terms: thinking (shiryo(s)), not-thinking (fushiryo(t)) and
without-thinking (hishiryo(u)). For our purposes here, the crucial
point to notice is that both thinking (any sort of conceptual
categorization, whether explicit or implicit) and not-thinking (the
denial or the lack of all such conceptualizations) are inappropriate
characterizations of the zazen state. Rather, the true mode of zazen
is without-thinking, a responsive state of awareness which is neither
thinking nor not-thinking, but which underlies the two. In fact, Dogen
implies that without-thinking takes the form of either thinking or
not-thinking. The importance of this point is that, by Dogen's
principle of the oneness of practice and enlightenment
(shushoichinyo(v)), without-thinking must somehow be authentication
itself. Thus, if we can understand without-thinking, we will also
understand Dogen's view of enlightened interpretation.
-
There are two
ways in which the self-reflexive test of corresponding within
consciousness can take place. For our example, we can refer to Dogen's
discussion of the interpretation of time in his fascicle "Being-time"
(Uji(w) ). First, an interpretation may be evaluated reflectively.
This is, in effect, a test for consistency in the concepts that
constitute one's interpretation of time. Dogen considers the
characterization of time as "flying away" (p. 191). In such a case,
Dogen urges us to "investigate" (kaie suru(x) or gaku suru(y)) the
matter. If time flies away, Dogen points out, then there is a
separation between oneself and time, between things and time. That is,
time itself is being considered a temporal thing.
-
Since this is
nonsensical, the interpretation cannot be definitive, Here we have the
authenticating response (without-thinking) assuming the form of
thinking. The self-reflexive evaluation may also be no reflective and
no conceptual, however. Thus, Dogen refers to the fact that people
often interpret temporal experiences as something they have, rather
than as what people are. To someone who has the wrong interpretation
here, Dogen merely calls on him or her to "Look! Look!" (p. 191). It
is significatn, by the way, that Lin-chi uses the same exhortation in
urging his disciples to see the true person within themselves. Here, I
argue the without-thinking authentication takes the form of
not-thinking, that is, the test takes the form of a prereflective,
nonconceptual "just looking."
-
From our
account of the Ch'an and Zen tradition, we can sec the rationale
behind this twofold process of authentication. Since things are
present to us as they really are, falsehood resides in our
interpretive processes. Dogen is correct in seeing two ways in which
these may lead us astray. First, we may develop inconsistent
interpretations which obviously cannot describe reality without
equivocation and ambiguity. Second, we may lose contact with what we
directly experience, that is, we may develop a nest of interconnected
concepts that are consistent among themselves, but simply do not
correspond to things (or, what is the same in the Zen view, to things
as directly experienced). The dual testing process, therefore, attacks
falsehood from both sides. A few clarifications are needed. First of
all, we are not always aware of our interpretations; in fact, they
need not even be verbalized to play a constitutive role in our
actions, feelings, and lines of thinking. Expressing this
phenomenologically, any positing attitude of an act of consciousness
involves interpretation. How then are we to become aware of such tacit
orientations? "Jijuyuu sammai itself is the touchstone," that is, in
the meditative state of zazen one is in direct contact with things as
they are. Therefore, any implicit assumption that is not a direct
reflection of this immediate experience will become manifest through
Zen practice. This does not mean that every such interpretation is
false; rather, they merely require further authentication. Consider,
for example, a stick's appearing bent when it is half-submerged in
water. The Zen stipulation is that the raw appearance is itself
truly-so; the bent stick's appearance is not itself false. Yet,
insofar as we do not expect the stick to be bent when we take it out
of the water, there must be a tacit assumption here that requires
authentication. In this case, the authentication process takes the
form of thinking, not just looking. We might, for instance, recall
previous experiences wherein being straight in the air is succeeded by
being bent in the water and vice versa. Therefore, by induction one
expects the same situation to prevail here. In other words, in this
example thinking relates the present, direct experience to previous
direct experiences such that we see the consistency in the
interpretation. It is significant that (unlike most of the Western
tradition) the Zen view does not require a scientific explanation of
why straight things appear bent when partially submerged, of what
causes the "same" really straight stick to appear bent. In the Zen
framework, interpretation must meet the requirements of accurate
description not adequate explanation. In this case, the interpretation
accurately describes what is now directly experienced in light of what
will be directly experienced (using what has been directly experienced
as the basis for the expectation). Thus, even though the
interpretation is not a simple reflection of the present experience,
it is still a reflection of a set of direct experiences. Hence, the
interpretation is authenticated.
-
A further
clarification concerns the term "correspondence." As noted earlier,
for their definition of the meaning of truth, Aristotle and Thomas
speak of the correspondence between mind and things, but for the test
of truth, the correspondence takes place within the intellect (which
is capable of both discursive and intuitive insights, incidentally).
Since the Zen tradition rejects the notion of false things, the
distinction between the two correspondences tends to collapse. In this
sense, the Zen view is that correspondence takes place between
experiential components.
-
Accordingly,
when there is correspondence, there is a unified consciousness without
dualism. When interpretations are authenticated, there is no gap
between the understanding and the experience. In Zen terminology, one
knows directly just as one knows that the water is cold when one
drinks it. This lack of opposition, this oneness of mind, is the basis
of the jijuyuu in jijuyuu sammai.
-
A third
clarification concerns the interrelationships among thinking,
not-thinking, and without-thinking. We might, for example, ask the
following question: how do we know when we should authenticate through
thinking and when we should do so through not-thinking? It is
important to bear in mind that this question again overlooks the
centrality of zazen (or jijuyuu sammai): we do not decide;
without-thinking spontaneously takes on the form of the appropriate
response. As Dogen puts it, the jijuyuu sammai itself is the
touchstone. In other words. to authenticate one need only be authentic
to oneself and to be authentic to oneself, one lets oneself show
itself without thinking about it. But how does one authenticate
whether one is being authentic? In the beginning, at least, one cannot
do this for oneself. A Zen master is necessary for guidance. Through
the encounter with the master, any traces of inauthenticity are made
manifest to the disciple until the disciple learns the serenity of
jijuyuu sammai. From that point onward, the presence of the serenity
is itself the authentication of the authenticity. In this respect,
zazen is the alpha and omega of Zen practice. This leads Dogen to
advocate shikantaza(z) , the performance of zazen alone. There is one
corollary to Dogen's position that deserves our attention here,
namely, the notion that truth (in its acquisition) is context
dependent.
-
Thus, in his
fascicle "Things' Being Present as They Are" (Genjokoan, p. 9), Dogen
follows the Yogaacaara view that the fish is correct in his belief
that the ocean is an emerald-like palace and the deva in heaven is
correct in his belief that the ocean is a glittering string of lights,
and the person far out at sea is correct in his belief that the ocean
is a great circle. The fish, the person, and the deva are each
authenticating what is actually experienced, given their respective
contexts. This, of course, violates the spirit of the views of both
Aristotle and Thomas. To see the implications of the difference, let
us refer back to Thomas' discussion of truth in art. Thomas maintained
that artworks are true insofar as they adequately take on the form of
the artists' intentions. From Dogen's standpoint, we can develop a
different theory of truth in art. That is, Dogen would presumably say
that the situation (the presence of tathataa) takes form through the
artist. Consider, for example, the creation of Michelangelo's "David."
According to historical accounts. Michelangelo claimed that he had
"seen" the image of
David in the
slab of marble discarded by another artist. That is, the marble
presented itself to Michelangelo as "David"
and Michelangelo became the vehicle for the thing's self-expression.
In the
Ch'an
and Zen terminology we have developed the image of
David in the
marble was a true thing and Michelangelo, acting as a true person, let
the thing show itself through him. This is why, as we have already
seen in the earlier quotation, Dogen associates jijuyuu sammai with
wu-wei. The artist, the Zen master, the Taoist sage are only insofar
as they are responsive to situations in which things present
themselves as they are; there is no self-conscious, calculative
"doing."
-
In fact,
Dogen considers language in its most profound usage, what Dogen calls
"expression" (dotoku(aa)), to be a creative activity like the one just
described. That is, language does not here refer to a preexistent
reality, but rather, things express themselves through the transparent
medium of without-thinking. In this way, the entire world of
phenomena-including the mountains, rivers and rocks-express reality.
Dogen, therefore, says that such things are themselves suutras (see,
for example, Dogen's fascicle, "The Mountain and Water Suutra,"
Sansuikyo(bb)).
-
This
concludes our discussion of truth and Zen Buddhism. Our major
conclusions are the following. First of all, although the
correspondence theory may give an adequate definition of truth, it
needs to be supplemented if we want to know how it is possible for
such a truth to be acquired in practice. We have investigated here the
threefold metaphysical account of truth first stated by Aristotle and
developed by Thomas, but also paralleled in the Ch'an and Zen
traditions. In general, we have found the threef old distinction to be
illuminating of the metaphysical assumptions behind correspondence as
a practical theory. Second, despite many startling similarities, we
must conclude that the Western view and the Zen view of truth are
fundamentally different, especially with respect to what the theory of
truth should try to accomplish. Ultimately, Aristotle and Thomas
desire a theory of truth that will be the cornerstone for explanatory
interpretation. Thomas adds to this the application of the theory to
events wherein things conform to mind, that is, to events wherein man
is in creative transformation of his world. Both explanation and the
governance of the natural world, we may note, are constitutive of an
idea of science. Beyond these goals,
Thomas
(and, to a lesser extent, Aristotle) is also interested in
establishing truth as a moral ideal of interpersonal relations, a
virtue toward which we should strive if we are to achieve our basic
humanity. The Zen view of truth, on the other hand, has a
distinctively different orientation. Rather than explanatory
interpretation, Zen is interested in descriptive interpretation.
Rather than governing the trans-formation of nature, the Zen Buddhist
tries to be the agent of nature. Rather than setting a moral standard
to live up to, the Zen Buddhist achieves his humanity by letting go of
external standards of value and by becoming more spontaneous. In the
final analysis, therefore. the Western philosophers stipulate a
tension between man and world: as Thomas put it, the mind must conform
to things and things to the mind. Harmony is achieved through mutual
adaptation. Zen philosophy, on the other hand, stipulates an essential
unity: the tension between man and world is the result of egocentric
delusion. If we destroy that delusion, man's activity his thinking and
his doing becomes just an expression of nature itself.
-
A final
lesson of our comparison is this: the Zen Buddhists do not think
differently than the Western philosophers. When it comes to defining
truth and articulating the metaphysical assumptions behind the
practieal application of this theory, the difference between the
traditions is slight. The Zen and Aristotelian/Thomistic traditions
diverge only when they consider what the purpose of thinking is and
what the basic relationship between man and world is.
-
Aristotle/Thomas and Hui-neng/Lin-chi/Dogen are not sets of writers
who think differently; they are groups of philosophers who disagree
about what we should think about.
-
-
REFERENCES
-
Quotations
from Aristotle are taken from Richard McKeon, ed., The Basic Works of
Aristotle (New York: Random House, 1969).
-
Quotations
from Thomas are taken from The Summa Theologica of St. Thomas Aquinas,
trans., Fathers of the English Dominican Province, 3 vols. (Benziger
Brothers, 1947) .
-
Quotations
from Lin-chi are translated from the Chinese original as given in
Sasaki, Record of Lin-chi (Kyoto: Institute for Zen Studies, 1975).
-
Two
references are given for quotations: the first number is correlated to
the Yanagida Rinzairoku edition as given in Schloegl, The Zen Teaching
of Rinzai (Boulder, Colorado: Shambala, 1976), while the second number
refers to the chapters as found in Sasaki.
-
Quotations from Dogen are translated from Okubo, ed., Dogenzenji
zenshu, vol 1. (Tokyo: Chikume Shobo, 1969).
--o0o--
|
|