The Virtues Approach
By James Whitehill
Stephens College
ISSN 1076-9005. Volume 1 1994
---o0o---
Abstract:
Contemporary Buddhism increasingly seeks to make itself
understood in modern terms and to respond to contemporary conditions.
Buddhism's legitimation in the West can be partially met by
demonstrating that Buddhist morality is a virtue-oriented,
character-based, community-focused ethics, commensurate with the
Western "ethics of virtue" tradition.
The recent past in Western Buddhist ethics focused on
escape from Victorian moralism, and was incomplete. A new generation
of Western Buddhists is emerging, for whom the "construction" of a
Buddhist way of life involves community commitment and moral
"practices." By keeping its roots in a character formed as "awakened
virtue" and a community guided by an integrative soteriology of wisdom
and morality, Western Buddhism can avoid the twin temptations of
rootless liberation in an empty "emptiness," on the one hand, and
universalistic power politics, on the other. In describing Buddhist
ethics as an "ethics of virtue," I am pointing to consistent and
essential features in the Buddhist way of life. But, perhaps more
importantly, I am describing Buddhist ethics by means of an
interpretative framework very much alive in Western and Christian
ethics, namely, that interpretation of ethics most recently associated
with thinkers like Alasdair MacIntyre and Stanley Hauerwas. The virtue
ethics tradition is the Western tradition most congenial to the
assumptions and insights of Buddhist ethics. Hence, virtue ethics
provides a means of understanding Buddhist ethics... and,
reciprocally, Buddhist ethics also offers the Western tradition a way
of expanding the bounds of its virtue ethics tradition, which has been
too elitist, rationalistic, and anthropocentric. On the basis of this
view, I predict some likely, preferable future directions and limits
for Buddhism in a postmodern world.
Introduction
My purpose in this article is to speculate about the
optimal, future development of Buddhism in the West. To speculate
about the future is, of course, to reach beyond the narrow protections
of expertise into the vulnerability of guesswork. My guesswork about
Western Buddhism's future takes the form of two hypotheses for
scholarly consideration by interested philosophers and ethicists,
Buddhist or not. The two hypotheses can also be viewed by Western
Buddhists as recommendations on the future course of their Buddhist
practices and communities.
The first hypothesis and recommendation is that Buddhism must begin to
demonstrate a far clearer moral form and a more sophisticated,
appropriate ethical strategy than can be found among its contemporary
Western interpreters and representatives, if it is to flourish in the
West. This hunch is to me almost certainly correct, so I will treat it
only briefly at the beginning.
My second conjecture is that Buddhism's success in the
West is most likely if Buddhist ethics is specifically grafted to and
enriched by the "ethics of virtue" approaches of Western tradition,
approaches recently revived in Christian thinkers like MacIntyre and
Hauerwas.(1) This second guess is more specific, tentative, and
provocative, and, therefore, more interesting, so it will be my
dominant theme (2) Viewing Buddhist morality and ethics in the light
of virtues theory is, I believe, true to the central core of Buddhism.
The virtues approach also generates a wide range of analytical
comparisons with Western philosophical and theological tradition, and
helps us foresee and plan for the limits of Buddhism's Western
pilgrimage.
Returning for a moment to my first and most general
hypothesis, I will begin by saying that I am persuaded that Buddhism
is on the threshold of a more significant future in the West. It will
increasingly play practical, heuristic, balancing, and liberating
roles in the lives of Western people and their societies. But, in
order for this to happen, philosophers, Buddhist and non-Buddhist,
must help more to clarify the moral and ethical terms of Buddhism's
soteriological project, in ways coordinate with Western intellectual
tradition. For more than two decades, Buddhist philosophical talent in
the West has been focused almost exclusively on ontology and
hermeneutics. One result is that Buddhist philosophy in the West has
ballooned off into the clouds of "sūnyatā-focused dialectics. I
propose that our philosophical soaring needs the ballast of Buddhist
moral practices and the landmarks of a refreshed Buddhist ethics to
bring Buddhist philosophy more into a practical relationship with the
on-the-ground, everyday realities of people's lives. I am moved to
this recommendation by my deductive understanding of Buddhist
teaching, but also by the fact that American Buddhists, since the
early 1980's, have increasingly puzzled over moral and/or political
choices and issues, without much help from Buddhist philosophers and
scholars who are also well-grounded in Western moral and political
thought.
When Christians translated their Gospel into Chinese
contexts, the Greek "Logos" became the Chinese "Tao," a daring and
radical translation, transmuting the Gospel as it transmitted it. A
similar translation problematique faces us now as Buddhism transmits
the "Dharma" to the West. But, in the matter of that part of the
Dharma which can be called "Buddhist ethics," no proposal in Western
philosophical terms on the shape of Buddhist ethics currently commands
wide attention, much less agreement.(3) As a result, the
legitimization of the Buddhist Dharma as a whole is at risk in the
West, for no religious or soteriological philosophy without a
developed ethic can be fully and widely legitimized in Western
culture.
A variety of philosophical proposals relevant to the
Western shaping of Buddhist ethics can be seen across the spectrum of
Buddhist thinkers. Happily, no one argues that Buddhist ethics or
morality are sui generis, a unique and inviolate form of Buddhist
tradition to be transplanted whole and entire into Western cultural
soil. Also, few are suggesting that Buddhist morality and ethics are
so much embedded in Asian cultures that they cannot be transplanted.
Both in theory and in practice, most Western Buddhists
appear to look for and accept a grafting or hybridizing process,
assimilating Buddhist moral stock to a plausible, compatible Western
moral root. Some are tempted to confuse this process, by reversing it,
as if the task is to graft Western moral concerns to a Buddhist root
of compassion or, worse, transcendental wisdom. This confusion is like
"growing a lotus without planting it in the mud," or "putting the
spiritual cart before the moral horse." More simply, this confusion
assumes that ethics follows spirit or theory, a rather un-Buddhist
notion, given the Buddha's existential impatience with metaphysical
gymnastics.
In the 1960's, Buddhist ethical reflection, and morality
in the broad sense of "a way of life," were grafted by Western
apologists to the stem of existentialism and to some branches of the
human potential movement.(4) These early efforts fell short of a
satisfactory ethical development of Western Buddhism, in my opinion,
because they failed to include much critical, communal, or practical
guidance for would-be Buddhist existentialists (or existentialist
Buddhists?) and other Aquarians. Recently, more politically relevant
splicings have been attempted by several Buddhists within the peace,
environmental, and feminist movements.(5)
Only a few Western philosophers have attempted grafting
work recently in Buddhist ethics, usually by asserting and working out
conceptual analogies between Buddhist ethics in general and particular
Western philosophers and theologians. Examples of this comparative
work include David Kalupahana's proposal that Buddhist ethics melds
interestingly with William James' pragmatism, and Christopher Ives'
explorations of opportunities to develop a Zen Buddhist social ethic
in contrast with Reinhold Niebuhr's Christian social ethics. Also
noteworthy, if less comparative in its analysis, is Robert Thurman's
proposal to find a relevant recipe for contemporary social activism in
a specific text of Nāgārjuna.(6)
While I do not find these proposals sufficiently developed
to be compelling to Western ethicists, they are thought-experiments
that address some issues of interest to Western philosophical and
theological ethics, while taking interpretive risks for the sake of
Buddhist relevance. I regret that none of the proposals can withstand
the kind of friendly critique that comes quickly and easily from
ethicists grounded in Christian and Western ethical studies; Winston
King, for example, has long been helpful in raising a variety of
critical and disturbing questions about the strengths and weaknesses
of Buddhist philosophy in a Western ethical milieu dominated by
demands for human rights and individual autonomy.(7)
Assuming the under-developed condition of the domain of
Buddhist ethics in Western context, I now address at length my second,
more tentative conjecture on the future prospect of Western Buddhism.
I propose that the most appropriate analogy, the most fruitful
grafting prospect for a Western Buddhist ethics, will be with the
Western tradition of the "ethics of virtue." By "ethics of virtue" I
mean simply an ethics that is character-based (rather than
principle-driven or act-focused), praxis-oriented, teleological, and
community-specific. More fully, I mean the complex tradition of ethics
that stretches in the West from Socrates and Aristotle to Alasdair
MacIntyre, Philippa Foot, and other contemporary virtues theorists.
increasing notice."(8)
This proposal does not originate with me. The conceptual
and heuristic linkage of Buddhist ethics with Aristotle's is a key to
Damien Keown's approach in his well-argued, revisionist view of
Buddhist ethics, The Nature of Buddhist Ethics.(9)
Earlier, Robert Bellah favored grafting Buddhism to the
virtues approach as a possible path to meet his concern to renew an
American ethic of community. Specifically, Bellah has called for a
"cultural symbiosis" of Zen and modern Aristotelianism as a way of
re-asserting "a teleological understanding of the order of human life"
and bringing about "the creation of actual communities" that can
resist:
- A modern Western culture that is destroying the natural
habitat, undermining any kind of social solidarity, and creating a
conception of the individual person which is utterly
self-destructive.(10)
The utopian spirit of his call for Buddhist-like
communities of personal and civic virtue suggests that these
communities would almost certainly be "marginalized," growing only at
the edges of the dominant socio-cultural structures of Western
individualism or bureaucratic nation-states. Its utopian character
does not seem to dissuade Bellah from making his recommendation. Nor
am I. Indeed, such "contrast" communities already exist, however
tenuous their rooting in the Western "soul and soil."(11)
Before taking up this proposal, that Buddhist "morality"
and "ethics" can be appropriately transplanted in the West by
assimilating them to our own virtues tradition, I need to define
Buddhist morality more precisely, in the terms of "awakened virtue."
"Awakened, compassionate virtue-cultivation" is a more accurate
phrasing of what I mean, but, for simplicity's sake, I will avoid
using it. "Awakened virtue" usefully describes the process and goal of
Buddhist morality. It affirms the intertwined correspondence of the
moral and the spiritual, in fresh language, by referring to Buddhist
moral vision and praxis in the language of virtues theory, and by
retaining the Buddhist insistence on spiritual awakening as a
necessary, although not sufficient, condition of moral maturity.
Second, I will simply define Buddhist ethics as "philosophical
reflection upon Buddhist morality, including descriptive, normative
and meta-ethical reflections."(12)
My purpose in this essay about "awakened virtue" is not to
engage in historical and textual analysis. I will not exegete the
comparative analogies of "sīla or the pāramitās (13)to phronesis,
arete, or virtus.(14) My aim is more philosophical, practical, and
even policy-oriented: to probe constructively the implications of
"awakened virtue," the goal of Buddhist morality and the object of
Buddhist ethics, in connection with the future prospects of Western
Buddhism. The effort to construct a Western Buddhist ethics by means
of a virtues approach is not without exemplars. For example, Robert
Aitken relies on it often in his homiletical text, The Mind of Clover:
Essays in Zen Buddhist Ethics. Aitken fashions refreshing sermons on
Buddhist ethics, with a Zen twist, framing most of his chapters as
expositions of "The Ten Grave Precepts" of Buddhist morality. He also
writes briefly about the Six Perfections, the six pāramitās of
generosity, morality, patience, vigor, meditation, and
self-realization, and discusses "virtue" as a way of understanding the
Zen life.
Aitken opens his chapter, "The Way and Its Virtue," with a
saying of his teacher, Yamada Koun Roshi: "The purpose of Zen practice
is the perfection of character." Aitken proceeds to discuss briefly
but provocatively the six pāramitās, relating them to contemporary
experience and applications.(15)But his teacher's saying is overlooked
and the focus on virtue collapses as, in the perennial fashion of most
Zen interpreters, he concludes that:
- At the same time, "virtue," "the Six Pāramitās,"
"perfection of character" -- these are simply labels for an organic
process. Breathing in and out, you let go of poisons and establish the
serene ground of the precepts.(16)
Aitken here falls into a common pitfall in the path of
ancient and contemporary Zen interpreters, what I call "the
transcendence trap." The trap misleads them and us into portraying the
perfected moral life as a non-rational expressiveness, something
natural, spontaneous, non-linguistic, and uncalculating. This is a
"Taoist-like" view of virtue as "natural, intuitive, skill/power"
(Chin., te; Jap., toku), a view Aitken shares with some influential,
but late Mahāyāna sūtras. This ethical conception results in the kind
of ontological dismissal of morality and ethics preached by Aitken at
the end of his chapter: "Thus, in the world, too, there is nothing to
be called virtue."(17) The common corollary, "there is also nothing to
be called character," is unstated by Aitken, although it is part of
the same syllogistic net of claims deduced ostensibly from "no-ego"
and "sūnyatā axioms. The net is true and helpful only within the
"deconstructive" mood and context of sunyata dialectics and
metaphysics. When the net of "no-self" is thrown to catch truth in an
ethical context, villains laugh and demons thrive.
A good beginning by Aitken, in taking a virtues approach
to interpreting Buddhist ethics, is later swamped by the "sūnyatā-weighted
dialectical anamorphisms of Mahāyāna and Zen thought. Aitken is
enmeshed in what I have called "the satori perspective" in Zen
philosophy, the position most clearly seen in DṬ.
Suzuki's vigorous anti-rationalism and antinomianism. The "satori
perspective" characteristically over-emphasizes the "awakening"
dimensions of Buddhist soteriology, to the detriment of the moral,
"virtuous" dimensions.(18) Consequently, a view of the Buddhist
virtues from this standpoint tends insistently to relativize and
diminish the "virtue" in the summum bonum of "awakened virtue," until
there is only the "awakened One," beyond good and evil.
A clear and egregious example of this spiritualizing
over-emphasis on "awakening," comes to us in the writings of Gerta
Ital, in her book, On the Way to Satori, where she offers us this
advice:
- This is something that cannot be repeated often enough:
no one who has not completely erased themselves as an ego can do
anything to help liberate anyone else, and the attainment of the goal
is not easy. The journey is very long .... Until one is liberated
oneself one is simply not capable of helping anyone else.(19)
This is not a complete Buddhism, I believe, and certainly
not one that can expect a significant future in the West, except as an
individualistic, private, and mainly "therapeutic" mysticism. Buddhism
is far more and other than that.
A fuller and more finely articulated virtues approach to
Buddhist ethics guides Ken Jones' The Social Face of Buddhism. I
consider this the best available ethical manual on Buddhist social
ethics by a Westerner.(20) I recommend it, convinced that it is a
touchstone philosophical text in Buddhist ethics. It is unlike
Aitken's, because Jones' seriously pays attention to key
philosophical, moral, and psychological issues. Regrettably, Jones,
like Aitken, walks into "the transcendence trap," by devaluing the
roles of will and deliberation in the life of awakened virtue.
Jones affirms in good virtues theory fashion that Buddhist
morality is a matter of character and cultivation, and that it focuses
on cultivating character rather than evaluating particular acts.(21)
But quickly he slides toward "the transcendence trap," beginning with
a too casual substitution of the word "personality" for
"character"(22):
- The emphasis in Buddhist morality is therefore on the
cultivation of a personality which cannot but be moral, rather than
focusing upon the morality of particular choices and acts. But, to
repeat, it is not the will that can create such a personality, no more
than I can pick myself up from the ground by my collar. It is to the
training that the will must be applied, from which virtue will
naturally flow (emphasis mine).(23)
Jones's disclaimer on the power of will may only be a
rejection of Nietzchean or Sartrean voluntarism. If so, he would be
correct from a Buddhist point of view, which dialectically affirms
both the deterministic weight of karma or character dispositions and
our freedom from them in the concomitant "emptiness" of "sūnyatā. And
he is certainly correct to assert that the will in Buddhist practice,
rather than serving a "creative" role in free self-creation, serves
mainly to restrain and hold oneself in the various forms of moral and
intellectual practice.
However, the fuzziness of the phrase, "from which virtue
will naturally flow," places Jones on the lip of the "transcendence
trap." He later falls in by constructing virtue as a kind of natural
"grace," emergent from the forms of moral discipline and
repetition,/yet different from them, somehow transcendent, natural and
free. As Robert Scharf suggests, this transcendent view of virtuous
activity is a mystification of what in Buddhist practice is simply a
repetitive and normal process of learning to perform in certain ways
with skill; Hee-jin Kim, discussing what he calls the "heart of
Dogen's thought," refers to the process of Buddhist practice as
essentially something prosaic, "the ritualization of morality."(24)
More than Jones can or will admit, schooling in the forms
of virtue is a social, emotional, and cognitive process. Becoming good
is hardly a natural process in the sense suggested, of being the
non-voluntary, non-deliberative unfolding of a natural goodness.
Aristotle would agree: "While it is Nature that gives us our
faculties, it is not Nature that makes us good or bad.(25)The goal of
ethics is to become a person who does good or virtuous things freely
from the ground of a well-tempered character, supported by a matured,
resolute, and reasonable knowledge of what one is doing. The path of
Buddhism does not dissolve character (which is different from ego and
personality). It awakens and illuminates moral character and
establishes a "noble" selfhood in the wide, deep, expressive freedom
of creative forms of life and its perfections.
Jones's view of virtue echoes the Christian moral doctrine
of "infused virtue," but without dependence on St. Thomas Aquinas'
transcendent, theistic assumptions and absent his clear sense of the
endurance of the "natural" virtues in the perfected saints. I venture
the guess that, like Alan Watts and others who fall into "the
transcendence trap," Jones devalues the will in preferring "natural
expressiveness" (in the sense of what we are born with, natus), in his
beliefs about learning to be good, because of things that have little
to do with Buddhism, the Diamond Sūtra, and Mahāyāna dialectics. I
suspect that many a Westerner's "Taoist-like" misreading of Buddhist
ethics, as a form of individualistic naturalism, is mostly and often a
reaction to the West's residual Victorian morality -- a morality
characterized by and hated for its conceived overemphasis on
individual, rational self-discipline, strength of will, rigidity of
personality, and psychophysical repressions -- and from which
middle-aged and older Western Buddhists seem to be still trying to
make their escape. In their desire to escape, they share in a broader,
late 20th century Western shift to a moral outlook that prizes a
rather passive, non-judgmental tolerance of others, combined with a
preference for the spontaneous or ecstatic expression of impulses ...
at least and especially in contrast with the much maligned Victorians.
To disdain the necessary roles of will and reason in the
Buddhist moral process is to overlook the importance of both in early
Buddhism. Early Buddhism did not abandon reason, although it did not
rely on reason alone. Neither did early Buddhists overlook the
necessity of a steady will, even in the stages of Buddhist meditation
training. That will and reason were requisite accompaniments of the
good person is also evident in later additions to the six pāramitās
list, namely, the pāramitās of resolution, determination, strength,
and skillful means. Obviously, strength of will is necessary even in
samādhi exercises, in making the Bodhisattva vow, or in responding to
exhortations of the Zen masters to throw one's whole self and
attention into zazen or koan. Buddhist cultivation requires a constant
dose of what William James called "animal spirits" and doing the
difficult thing against our inclinations.
Now, having by-passed the "transcendence trap" on the way
to a Buddhist virtues perspective, I wish briefly to describe what I
mean by Buddhist "awakened virtue" in the context of general virtues
theory, distinguishing it somewhat from traditional Western views.
Following this description, I will conclude by exploring some
implications for the West of viewing Buddhist ethics and the Buddhist
"way of life" in a virtues perspective.
Buddhist Morality as Awakened Virtue
The Buddha's Dharma or teaching was authoritatively
divided in early times into three groups, but they were interdependent
facets of one process leading to deliverance (vimutti). The Buddhist
investigated and cultivated "sīla (morality), samādhi (deep
meditation), and prajñā (transcendental wisdom).(26) Each of the three
facets of self-cultivation evolved appropriate practices ... of moral
intention, behavior, and correction; of meditation method and mapping;
of transformative shifts of consciousness. We may speak of these
practices as the moral, contemplative, and transformative pāramitās.
The last, the transformative pāramitās, are concerned with practices
that alter consciousness on a transcendental, "Nirvanic" level, while
the contemplative pāramitās have to do with the development of powers
of concentration, stability, and tranquilization in meditation. The
moral pāramitās involve practices in which good intentions are aroused
and acted upon in the light of a right understanding of the good and
of situations. With repetition and correction these practices
severally and together nurtured the dispositions, both karmic and
salvific, that together constitute Buddhist character.
Why these pāramitās as the specific Buddhist virtues,
rather than others, invites a fuller treatment than I will give
here.(27) The pāramitās, as methods of attending, energizing,
pacifying and relating the self to others, work together to wean the
self from egocentricity. Beyond ego-weaning, the goal of the pāramitās
is positive: to foster a character that increasingly encounters each
moment, each space, each being, as a "mother" enjoys and protects her
only child ... to use a traditional simile attributed to the Buddha.
Since moral intentions are always elastic, they need
shaping by forms and disciplines, taught by teachers and learned in
communities. The virtuous practices that in Buddhism characterize a
good person were often defined as at least the six pāramitās of
generosity or gift-giving (dāna), morality or the Five Precepts ("sīla),
patience and forgiveness (kṣānti),
courage and vigor (vīrya), concentration (dhyāna), and wisdom (prajñā).
Some held that the six pāramitās constituted a progressive order of
training in virtue, from generosity to wisdom. These may be said to be
the necessary moral, mental, and spiritual touchstones of the Buddhist
virtues tradition, notwithstanding later additions to and analytical
divisions of the six. Enrichment of virtue-like practices beyond the
pāramitās is seen in the development of the well-known Four
Immeasurables (the Brahmavihāras or "divine abodes") of Buddhist
friendliness, compassion, joy, and peace, which further mapped out,
stimulated, and idealized Buddhist moral praxis.
These practices, moral and otherwise, were more often than
not "methodologized," that is, formalized, ritualized and
institutionalized in ways to promote habitual performances in a
general program of self-cultivation and character development,
conceived to stretch over many aeons of time (thus requiring the
pāramitā of patience!). Methods would differ somewhat between monk and
layperson, and from culture to culture. Some practices were Buddhist
adaptations of pre-existing practices and rituals in the surrounding
non-Buddhist culture, as Nath shows in her study of the Buddhist
transformations of Hindu dāna, gift-giving rites.(28)
Buddhist moral self-cultivation tends to encompass not
only the formation of good intentions in the heart and mind (reminding
us of Kant). Practices also include physical postures and
breath-speech techniques. This holistic "psycho-pneumo-physical"
approach to moral self-cultivation results, for example, in attention
to helping others not only by forming a good will, but also by
expressing kind words and offering the material things that they also
need. A more holistic self-training also opens a way to fuse moral
practice with aesthetic practice, as an early concern in Buddhism with
how gracefully to give gifts demonstrates.
Practice of the moral pāramitās is said to create and
accumulate "merit," or favorable karma dispositions within the psyche,
that lead to a better life and higher rebirth. The "ethics of karma,"
focused upon by Melford Spiro and Winston King as the key to
understanding Theravādin Buddhist societies, is when looked at closely
but an "ethics of karma-cultivating virtues and practices."(29) Spiro
and King, reflecting an interpretation within the Theravādin
tradition, highlight the ostensibly traditional split between the
karmic and the Nibbānic motives in Buddhist life, one for goodness and
reward, the other for salvation and transformative liberation. The two
motives are personalized in layperson and monk, respectively.(30)
The tension between moral and religious motives appears
also in Mahāyāna Buddhism. At one point the tension was reconciled in
the bodhisattva image of a virtuous layman-sage, Vimalakīrti. The
Vimalakīrti Sūtra affirms that a breach between moral effort and
spiritual awakening constitutes bondage and delusion.(31) The center
of Buddhist tradition affirms that moral effort, mainly through
practicing the pāramitās, must be conjoined with meditative and
transformative practices to be ultimately effective for oneself and
for others. It also affirms that the practices of awakening have
little foundation and less result, for oneself or others, without the
frame, skills, and habit of moral practice. Moral virtue without "sūnyatā,
or transforming liberation, may be shallow and weak; but "sūnyatā
without moral virtue is blind and dangerous. She who has accomplished
awakened virtue, the merging of skilled, well-disposed, rational moral
agency with self-transforming spirit, is, in contrast, deep, strong,
ever-maturing, and rational, ... by her character and deeds she
reduces suffering and promotes friendliness, compassion, joy, and
peace.
In contrast with Western virtues tradition, the Buddhist
pāramitās viewpoint tends, in matters of self and community, to be
biocentric and ecological. First, Buddhism does not begin with the
premise of the substantial, separable, and distinctive self of
Aristotelian and Christian thought. In Buddhism, the idea of the
atomistic, self-empowering monad-godling of Western individualism is
well known, but understood as a delusion born of ignorant desires and
fears, resulting in a wish-fantasy for domination. Compared to Western
concepts, the self-concept of Buddhism is processional, relational,
and "fuzzy."(32)
While the moral saint as individualized hero, above and
apart from others, is not unknown in Buddhism, the open, relational
nature of selfhood stresses the solidarity of those who act virtuously
with those for whom they act or, better, with whom they practice the
perfecting goods of generosity, patience, and so forth. For Buddhist
thought the self is fundamentally incomplete, evolving, and
interpenetratively co-dependent with others. Since we are imbedded in
mutual dependent community, training in the pāramitās, moral and
otherwise, is necessarily a training with others and for others.
Because of this solidarity and because pāramitās practice nurtures
body, speech, and the mind-heart, the Buddhist believes her moral
efforts flow necessarily into the community on many levels,
materially, verbally, and mentally, in a subtle, looping reciprocity.
Second, Buddhist tradition differs from the Western in
defining membership in the moral community, the "considered others" to
whom pāramitās-defined practices are to be extended. In the dominant
traditions of Western culture, at least since Aristotle, the community
of character and virtue has clearly been the human community. The
politics in which an individual's ethics and virtue find their
completion is a human politics - almost always an anthropocentric,
urban politics. The Buddhist community of virtue is biocentric, far
more inclusive of animals and other sentient beings as objects of
moral consideration (in the practice of the six pāramitās, for
example, giving aid to animals) than Western virtues tradition.(33)
Because of this biocentric orientation, Buddhist moral practices must
include specific training and self-cultivation in our relations with
nature, as well as human society, extending dāna, "sīla, kṣānti,
and so on to non-human sentient beings and to the biosphere itself as
a community of communities.(34)
Given the exurban settings of Buddhist monasteries and
universities, and other factors, Buddhist ethics did not elaborate
itself often into urban, class-oriented political theory, a theory of
revolutionary change, or a theory legitimizing divine rule... although
Buddhist thinkers did propose all three. The community scale imaged by
the saṃgha
was smaller and more nurturing of personal development, perhaps that
of a village set within nature. Perhaps this goes to explain partially
why even urban Buddhists have tended to re-create or simulate in the
grounds of their city temples a contrasting, natural refuge, for
people, animals, fish, birds, and even insects. A Japanese tea
ceremony garden and hut in the middle of Tokyo express this microtopic,
exurban focus most eloquently and ironically.
Like the Aristotelian virtues tradition, Buddhist ethics
tends to be ahistorical, in that it regards human life as having an
important and profound constancy in its nature and goal, persistent
amidst the general flow and struggles of actual personal and
historical forces. That constancy for the Buddhist lies not in a
substantial or eternal self, but in our common, almost irrefragable
experience of suffering and in our inherent capacity to work toward an
awakened, moral virtuosity, in wisdom and fellow-feeling.
With respect to the question of historicity, I think that,
in comparison with the Christian virtues tradition, Buddhist ethics
did not develop so extensive a quasi-historical hagiography, a "sense
of narrative," concerning the lives of the virtuous and their
exemplars, the saints. The Jātaka Tales, while we classify them as
"animal" fables, may be similar in appearance to a "Lives of the
Saints." But we should probably resist calling them "narrative"
because they display a narrow range of the Buddhist reality picture,
and we should hesitate to call them unqualifiedly Buddhist, because
the stories are from a pre-Buddhist tradition. This comparative
absence of emphasis on individual "drama," which may be more of degree
than type, applies even to the most obvious Buddhist saint, the
Buddha, whose "story" does not serve for Buddhists the whole range of
functions that we find centered in the Gospels, in Roman Catholic
hagiography or in Muslim hadith tradition.(35)
On another theme of contemporary virtues theory, I begin
by acknowledging without apology that Buddhism makes moral claims that
are universalistic. Buddhists have imagined utopian times and settings
for the virtuous, the perfected, the awakened ... and projected a
utopic future when "all beings are awakened." But, like all ethical
traditions centered on virtues, Christian, Muslim, Confucian, or
Aristotelian, the Buddhist pāramitā tradition looks to the
establishment of particular and appropriately designed communities to
optimize favorable conditions for self-cultivation and happiness in
the good life. Virtue ethics traditions, often focused in small groups
engaged in voluntary training, tend to spend little time on the
ethical strategies necessary in non-voluntary, pluralistic, very
large, or coercive societies. Consequently and not surprisingly, they
tend to lack a viable social ethic in modern terms, that is a
policy-generating set of principles that can be institutionalized on a
mass scale, while protecting individual rights-claims with coercive
means.
So, while espousing the general tenets and principles of a
universal ethics, Buddhist ethics tends, in practice, to define and
effectuate pāramitā-cultivation in community-specific terms. At the
mind-and-heart level, the broad intention "to help others" may be
similar across many communities, but at the levels of linguistic and
physical practice, the pāramitās have a local aspect, and in that
sense display a modest "historical" quality. For example, while the
virtue of giving, dāna-pāramitā, may show local nuances of expression
in almsgiving rites, these local forms are practiced with recognition
of their universal applicability in their intention, but not in their
formal, material, local features. A tolerant awareness of distinctions
between inner and outer aspects of Buddhist practices may result in
much less zealous enforcement of verbal, symbolic, and physical
conformity in moral (and contemplative) practices in Buddhist
contexts. The resulting diversity, flexibility, and tolerance sustain
the Buddhist tradition, at the risk of appearing very soft and highly
"contextual" in social ethics and politics.
Nevertheless, one does find conformity in the moral forms
and practices within Buddhist voluntary communities, of which the saṃgha
is the classical exemplar. Conformity is in keeping not only with the
needs of any community for the standardization and predictability of
behaviors that enhance trust and efficiency. Shared forms are
especially necessary and appropriate to a community guided by virtue
ethics. The Buddhist's cultivation of the pāramitās requires a
community designed to respond to awakened virtue practices with
specific structures of support and correction.
Each Buddhist community has a distinctive shape and style,
governed primarily by a common goal, the awakened virtue of each
member-in-community. This perfectionist aim is universalized and
idealized by extending it to encompass the awakening of "all sentient
beings." But, on-the-ground, the community's purpose is realized in
the details ... of distinctive forms of etiquette, and in the
characters of exemplary individuals; in shared schedules, and a common
submission to rules; in rituals of giving and receiving, and
procedures for correcting and expelling delinquent members. These are
communities where one learns and practices what it quite precisely
means, mentally and physically, morally and psychologically, to act as
an "awakened virtue being." That is, one learns to act, to perform, to
talk, walk, sit, sort things out, and take out the garbage like a
Buddha.
It should be obvious by now that learning to act like a
Buddha means something other than becoming spontaneous, inventive, and
free of Victorian inhibitions. The practice of awakened virtue in
Buddhist communities requires diligent learning of the forms in and
through which one can perform like an awakened virtue being. In the
moral sphere, these practices require repeated experiences in learning
how to give, to listen patiently, to call up courage in overcoming
fear and desire, to observe non-violence in the way one walks, to
steady the mind and heart, to make friends with the seasons, and so
on. In the meditative sphere, similar forms of practice are observed,
submitted to, tasted, repeated, tested, and perfected, in cultivation
of the contemplative virtues.
Finally, the Buddhist community, like any virtue-oriented
community, is defined in the characters of its persons, as well as in
their stories and the forms of their practices. Its continuation and
success depend necessarily upon the degree to which community members
become successful practitioners of the community's full repertoire of
virtues. Thus, Buddhism will flower in the West only when Western
Buddhists take up a fully balanced Buddhist way of life, by
cultivating both the moral and the contemplative pāramitās in proper
balance. "Awakened virtue" is the balanced platform upon which to
practice the ultimate, transformative, Nirvanic virtues constituting
the flowering of the spiritual life of Buddhists.
Implications for Buddhist Ethics in the West
If we accept the propositions that Buddhist ethics is
ineluctably and essentially an "ethics of virtue" and, second, that
the Buddhist life is necessarily at every stage integrative of moral
and spiritual practices, several implications emerge for Buddhism as
it grows in the West. Some of these implications are corrective of
recent Western Buddhist troubles, while others may indicate real
limits to Buddhism's success in and impact on the West.
Soon, with the passing away of the pioneering, older
generations of Western Buddhists, I hope we will see Buddhism in the
West turning from its role as a raft carrying Westerners away from the
eroding shores of Victorian -- or Judaeo-Christian -- or technological
-- or imperialist --or patriarchal culture. While the function of
Buddhism as a means of liberation from suffering and oppression is a
central one, it is not the only one. The other function of Buddhism is
to carry the suffering to the Other shore, to awakened virtue, to
becoming a Buddha in Buddha fields where Buddhas flourish. This means
working to construct and preserve relationships and communities, as
much as cultivating oneself. And this means the renewal of a pāramitās-approach
in Buddhist thought and life.
One corrective consequence of renewing the pāramitās in
Buddhist lives and communities will be the denial of authority to
imbalanced Buddhist teachers by the communities that support them. Too
many Buddhist teachers in the West in the 1980's have demonstrated
that they cannot balance well the moral and the spiritual.(36)
However, a virtues-oriented ethic has limitations in meeting problems
caused by the vices of individuals in the practicing community. This
is because a virtue ethic focuses on the person-as-agent developing
over time, in a learning process often of trial and error. This
long-term focus devalues the moral significance of particular acts,
even transvaluing them into "teachable moments," while often
overlooking the consequences of flawed or vicious acts for others and
the community. A particular moral failure is excused as
"out-of-character." The result is a greater tolerance of isolated acts
of harming others, for example, unless the acts constitute an
intolerable "pattern" of vice that forces community or individual
reaction ... perhaps too late.
Every virtue ethics guides us to the good life by means of
models of "the good person." The model may be a living person or a
narrative character (i.e., the Buddha, Vimalakīrti, Vessantara, Queen
"Srīmālā, one's roshi, etc.). A focus on character tends to obscure or
override the role of general principles and rules as guides to
decision-making and mutual regulation.
But rules, however flawed, sometimes have a place. For
example, a rule-orientation is preferable in some circumstances and
relationships to counter teacher-disciple abuses and distortions.
Traditionally, Buddhism depends heavily on its teachers and on the
belief that profound qualities of an awakened teacher can be passed
directly, through "mind-to-mind" transmission, to her students. Of
course, teachers are capable of transmitting the forms of the
pāramitās, moral and contemplative, through imitation,
familiarization, direct instruction, and, I will grant, a kind of
psychic "osmosis." But, far more difficult to transmit to one's
students and friends are the all-important balance and integration of
the pāramitās in a given person, because they are partly contingent on
the individuality of the novice's personality. It is wrong to believe
that this balance can be given to the student, rather than earned by
self-effort in the corrective view of a vital community.
Buddhist tradition poses to each Buddhist a momentous
question: "Who is Buddha?" How do we know that someone is advanced in
the practices of "awakened virtue"? That she's a "good person"? The
answer is critical, for it is these people one turns to for
instruction, advice, example, confidence, and even faith. A pāramitās-oriented
approach carries us some distance to the answer, because of its dual
focus on character and communally validated moral practices.
Consequently, the living meaning of awakened virtue is less dependent
on the character of single persons upon whom a community focuses, and
more dependent on several persons and the community (the saṃgha-community)
in its evolving solidarity. Viewing the practicing community as
Buddha, as itself a virtue-oriented awakening being, reduces
personality cults and deepens community resources.
The pāramitās emphasis I am advocating will tend to
develop protective standards of a more public nature, to test those
who seek to join or lead communities. But a Buddhist virtues approach
requires shoring up with useful ethical strategies developed in the
West both to assess particular acts and to generate moral rules. The
Western Buddhist milieu may also require a heuristic recovery of the
Vinaya tradition of Buddhist monastic regulation. The Vinaya may have
strayed into the trap of legalistic casuistry, but it did define and
set procedures for adjudicating particular acts of monks that could
not be tolerated, that had to result in suspension or expulsion.
Western Buddhist communities are only now beginning to face up to this
kind of decision-making, for which a virtues-orientation is sometimes
inadequate.
Having said all this, I acknowledge that act-evaluations
and rule-adjudications must be secondary instruments in Buddhist
ethics, necessary as they may be in particular moments of particular
communities. Essentially, Buddhist ethics is centered in and on
"character in community." This focus needs to be kept, for upon it
depends the future development of a Buddhist ethics more aimed at
relationships than principles, more interested in mutual support than
a defense of rights, more empathic than rational, more compassionate
than just.
Ethical strategies focusing on rational rules and
judgments of particular outward acts are the essential feature of
groups so large that they constitute a society of strangers,
threatened by the Hobbesian shadows of competition and governed by
laws of contract, restraint, coercion, property, and command.(37)Laws
are secondary to virtue in a Buddhist setting (and in this I agree
with Western Buddhists who resist "code" or rule-oriented moralizing
as a dominant approach to self- or community-discipline).
Nevertheless, while secondary, they are not dispensable.
The primary focus on persons, character, and virtuous
practices in Buddhist ethics cannot be sustained without community,
places where we know each other well enough to call each other into
the intimacies of an ethics of intention and practice, as in a family.
This means that Buddhist communities must ever be small, small enough
that people intimately know each other and the other sentient beings
sharing their life and death . I propose that they can be too small,
in that a group of four or six can hardly challenge and support the
full range of self-cultivation practices necessary to awakened virtue.
The problem of size for many Buddhists in the West lies at the "too
small" end of the spectrum. But that's better than to be at the "too
large" end. I cannot identify a practicing community that has become
too large (say, more than 200 active members), unless one looks at the
large metropolitan communities in San Francisco and Los Angeles, which
are arguably too large, too complex, and too absorbed in the entropic
tasks of organization maintenance of buildings, mortgages, and so on.
We know from reading Aristotle and MacIntyre that an
ethics focused in virtue does not picture the way to the good life in
abstract or individual or universal terms. The paths of virtue are
marked by lived practices special to each community. Virtue-oriented
groups and communities, if we are to believe MacIntyre and Hauerwas,
depend more on their traditional "narrative" reality- frames, their
memories and stories of good persons practicing the good life, than on
their laws or universal principles.(38) But, we also know that Western
Buddhists today live in a post-Nietzschean world, where the "stories"
are many and "memory" is tattered. It is not at all clear to many
Western people that their chosen or inherited stories invoke human
reality in a coherent and compelling way.
In the postmodern West, the Buddha's story or the life of
awakened virtue can be told and tested only in small, marginalized
zones appropriately distanced from the dominant power and value
structures. The criteria of testing are two: 1) the plausibility of
the story of a person who, through specific practices in a certain
kind of community, "awakened, by and through virtuous practices, in
wisdom and compassion;" and 2) the evident goodness in the people and
communities now engaged in practices of the Dharma. These people are
the Buddha. Their story is the Buddha's story.
Acceptance of the virtues approach in ethics presents
specific challenges and advantages to Buddhist thinkers and other
scholars. For example, we need to develop a more historical
scholarship of the pāramitās dimension in Buddhism. But, hopefully, we
can also help people in today's Buddhist communities to think through
the tensions among the pāramitās, the problems of priorities, the
meanings of practicing in lay life, and a host of other on-the-ground
issues. We need to help Western Buddhists distinguish among
therapeutic, aesthetic, moral, economic, political, and spiritual
practices and choices. What is the optimum balance of attention and
consideration between self and others? What is Buddhist friendship?
Does it include mosquitoes? How and why do Buddhists fail morally
after years of practice? How does a virtues orientation link up with
social justice issues and the development of a Buddhist social ethics?
Far more moral and ethical questions buzz in Western Buddhists' lives,
awaiting creative, practical inquiry by philosophers, new generation
Buddhologists, and others.
I have been recommending the virtues approach. It needs a
fuller development, in order to carry Buddhist morality into an
inevitable, serious and mutually constructive dialogue with Western
philosophers and theologians. My recommendations may appear too
straitlaced, or even atavistically Victorian, but what seems clear to
me so far is this. The most constructive future of Buddhism in the
West rests on its manifestation in the characters of people, not in
eloquent prose, fundraising efforts, temple-building, or incomplete
life modeling. Hopefully, a new generation will increasingly take the
path of balancing samādhi-exercise with pāramitās-practices. Put
simply, the future depends on a few good women and men who reveal a
balanced, integrative life -- of "awakened virtue" practices, in
families, jobs, and communities. It is through good lives that the
Buddha's Dharma can fully flower in the West, transforming our
sufferings and awakening in us, each and all, that which is best, inch
by inch, moment by moment, breath by breath.
Notes
(1) Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue 2nd ed. (Notre Dame,
Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984; Stanley Hauerwas, A
Community of Character (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame
Press, 1981).
(2) For my judgment that Buddhism will fail to bear fruit
in the United States unless it develops moral practices and ethical
reflection more in concert with American realities, see James
Whitehill, Enter the Quiet (San Francisco: Harper & Row, Publishers,
1980), 60-74, and Whitehill, "Is There a Zen Ethic?," The Eastern
Buddhist (New Series) 20 (Spring 1987), 9- 33.
(3) A promising and brief sketch of the philosophical
roots of Buddhist ethics in the doctrine of "dependent co-arising" (paṭicca-samuppāda),
with a good discussion of "moral agency", is Joanna Macy's "Dependent
Co-arising: The Distinctiveness of Buddhist Ethics," The Journal of
Religious Ethics, Vol. 7 No. 1 (Spring 1979), 38-52. But Macy did not
explicitly acknowledge the commensurability of Buddhist ethics with
virtue ethics, in terms of key similarities with respect to the nature
of the self, dispositions (kamma, sankhāras, etc.), and freedom.
(4) I think here first of the San Francisco Renaissance
figures of Jack Kerouac and Gary Snyder, but also of Erich Fromm,
William Barrett, Alan Watts, Thomas Merton, and other writers who
probed parallels between Zen and their own home-grown existential
concerns.
(5) Relevant sources include: (on feminism) Rita Gross,
"Buddhism and Feminism: Toward their Mutual Transformation," The
Eastern Buddhist 19 (Autumn 1986), 62-74; Sandy Boucher, Turning the
Wheel: American Women Creating the New Buddhism (San Francisco: Harper
& Row, Publishers, 1988); (on environmentalism) Allan H. Badiner, ed.,
Dharma Gaia (Berkeley: Parallax Press, 1990); J. Baird Callicott and
Roger T. Ames, eds., Nature in Asian Traditions of Thought (Albany:
S.UṆ.Y.
Press, 1989); James Whitehill, "Ecological Consciousness and Values:
Japanese Perspectives," Ecological Consciousness, eds. J. Donald
Hughes and George Schultz (New York: University Press of America,
1980), 165-182; (on the peace movement) Fred Eppsteiner, ed., The Path
of Compassion: Writings on Socially Engaged Buddhism (Berkeley:
Parallax Press, 1988).
(6) See David J. Kalupahana, "The Buddhist Conceptions of
"Subject" and "Object" and their Moral Implications," Philosophy East
and West 33 (July 1988), 290-304; Christopher A. Ives, "A Zen Buddhist
Social Ethic," (Unpublished PhḌ.
dissertation, Claremont Graduate School, 1988) and Zen Awakening and
Society (Honolulu: University of Hawai'i Press, 1992); Robert A.
Thurman, "Guidelines for Buddhist Social Activism Based on Nāgārjuna's
Jewel Garland of Royal Counsels," The Eastern Buddhist (New Series) 16
(Spring 1983), 19-51. For a Kantian approach, see Philip Olson, The
Discipline of Freedom: A Kantian View of the Role of Moral Precepts in
Zen Practice (Albany: State University of New York, Press, 1993).
Return
(7) See Winston L. King, "Buddhist Self-World Theory and
Buddhist Ethics," The Eastern Buddhist (New Series) 22 (Autumn 1989),
14- 26; "A Buddhist Ethic for the West?" (unpublished manuscript,
1990).
(8) A large bibliography of contemporary writings in
virtues theory is in Robert B. Kruschwitz and Robert C. Roberts, ed.,
The Virtues: Contemporary Essays on Moral Character (Belmont, Calif.:
Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1987), 237-63. For a discussion of the
translatability and commensurability of one ethical tradition (e.g.,
Buddhist) with another (e.g., Western virtues tradition), see Stephen
E. Fowl, "Could Horace Talk with the Hebrews? Translatability and
Moral Disagreement in MacIntrye and Stout," The Journal of Religious
Ethics Vol. 19 No.1 (Spring, 1991), 1- 20.
(9) Damien Keown, The Nature of Buddhist Ethics (New York:
St. Martin's Press, 1992). See especially Chap. 1, "The Study of
Buddhist Ethics," and Chap. 8, "Buddhism and Aristotle."
(10) Robert N. Bellah, "The Meaning of Dogen Today," Dogen
Studies, ed. William R. LaFleur (Honolulu: University of Hawai'i
Press, 1985), 157-8.
(11) "Soul and soil" because a complete virtue ethics not
only refers to the capacities of "human beings in general," but also
the particular limitations for expressing those capacities in terms of
the "soil," literally and metaphorically, in which those capacities
for "humanity at its best" are grown. Virtue is formed by "place," and
a change of place or soil requires appropriate transformation of the
virtues. Ivan Illich and others have called for a "philosophy of
soil," because "our generation has lost its grounding in both soil and
virtue. By virtue, we mean that shape, order and direction of action
informed by tradition, bounded by place, and qualified by choices made
within the habitual reach of the actor; we mean practice mutually
recognized as being good within a shared local culture which enhances
the memory of a place." See, "Declaration of Soil," Whole Earth
Review, No. 71 (Summer, 1991), 75.
(12) By "awakened," I mean the process and state of an
empowering liberation of the self, by means of ego-transforming
praxis. By "virtue," I mean the ideal cultivated set of rational
discernments, personal skills, and dispositions of character regarded
as ideal and relevant to relations with self and others in a known and
shared community, in this case the Buddhist community. In Buddhism as
I understand it, moral virtue and spiritual awakening are coordinate
and mutually necessary; neither alone is sufficient for attaining
Buddhahood.
(13) "Sīla, "custom or manner," but usually referring to
the Five Precepts, avoidance dicta, such as, "Avoid harming living
beings," etc. Pāramitā, "high," "complete," or "perfect," but usually
in the context of a list of "perfections," akin to the virtues,
characterizing the praxis and character of those pursuing the Buddhist
goals of selflessness, insight, compassion, and liberation or
"salvation."
(14) Several works can provide historical and textual
framework for Buddhist ethics, including H. Saddhatissa, Buddhist
Ethics (New York: George Braziller, 1970, and Gunapala Dharmasiri,
Fundamentals of Buddhist Ethics (Antioch, Calif.: Golden Leaves
Publishing Company, 1989). Lopez's recent discussion of virtues and
sainthood from the Mahāyāna bodhisattva perspective, with comparisons
to Roman Catholic tradition, is detailed enough to be helpful; Donald
S. Lopez, Jr., "Sanctification on the Bodhisattva Path," Sainthood,
eds. Richard Kieckhefer and George S. Bond (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1988).
(15) For a classic discussion of the pāramitās, "Sāntideva,
The Path of Light, trans. LḌ.
Barnett (AMS Press, 1990). A more recent translation of "Sāntideva's
Bodhicārya-avatāra is Marion Matics' Entering the Path of
Enlightenment (London: Macmillan Company, 1970).
(16) Robert Aitken, The Mind of Clover: Essays in Zen
Buddhist Ethics (San Francisco: North Point Press, 1984), 158.
(17) Aitken, The Mind of Clover, 159.
(18) See Whitehill, "Is There a Zen Ethic?"
(19) Gerta Ital, On the Way to Satori: A Women's
Experience of Enlightenment, trans. Timothy Green (Dorset, England:
Element Books, Ltd., 1990), 276.
(20) Ken Jones, The Social Face of Buddhism: An Approach
to Political and Social Activism (London: Wisdom Publications, 1989).
(21) Dharmasiri, interestingly, argues that Buddhist
ethics is best understood as a peculiar, non-hedonic form of act
utilitarianism; Fundamentals of Buddhist Ethics, 26-27.
(22) Much confusion in thinking about Buddhism in the West
results because the Asian cultures from which it comes focus morality
in the "roles" people play in hierarchical, organic relationships,
while modern Westerners who have taken up Buddhism are often urged by
their traditions to view morality from the perspective of the
autonomous, isolated self, understood as an expressive "personality."
This cross-cultural difference needs to be more carefully used and
understood by Buddhist interpreters. On the contemporary American
shift of interest from "character" to "personality," see Anthony
Quinton, "Character and Culture," in Vice and Virtue in Everyday Life,
ed. Christina & Fred Sommers (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovic,
Publishers, 1989), 613-22.
(23) Jones, The Social Face of Buddhism, 157.
(24) Robert H. Scharf, "Being Buddha: A Performative
Approach to Ch'an Enlightenment" (unpublished manuscript, 1989).
Hee-jin Kim, Dogen Kigen: Mystic Realist (Tucson: The University of
Arizona Press, 1987), 172-3. Martin Southwold argues, in the instance
of Sinhalese Buddhism, that ethical behavior is the focus and vehicle
of the "ritual impulse" for Buddhist laypeople in Sri Lanka. Absent a
transcendent focus of religious worship and ritual reference,
Buddhists have made of ethics and the Dharma the object of ritual
activity. Of course, the form of ethics most congenial to
ritualization is, of course, virtue ethics. See Southwold, Buddhism in
life: the anthropological study of religion and the Sinhalese practice
of Buddhism (Dover, NḤ.:
Manchester University Peress, 1983), 162-80.
(25) Nicomachean Ethics, Book I I, Chap. 4. See M.F.
Burnyeat, "Aristotle on Learning to Be Good," Essays on Aristotle's
Ethics, ed. Amelie Oksenberg Rorty (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1980), 69-92.
(26) I am taking a rather casual approach to the spelling
of these terms, choosing between the Pali and the Sanskrit renderings
on the basis of which seems easiest to pronounce and remember in
English. I am casual with an excuse however, for I think it must soon
be necessary to coin English phonetic neologues for these terms, and I
am merely choosing those I like (e.g., I think paññā is weak-sounding
in English when referring to a powerfully transforming insight, or
prajñā-insight.
(27) I hope someone with perseverance can attempt an
analysis of the pāramitās, in comparative light, akin to Lee Yearley's
arduous study of the theories of virtue in Mencius and Aquinas.
Yearley takes the study of virtue deep into comparative terrain,
marking assiduously more distinctions between Aquinas and Mencius than
I care to know, because I can't see readily what difference they make.
Lee Yearley, Mencius and Aquinas: Theories of Virtue and Conceptions
of Courage (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1990).
(28) Vijay Nath, Dāna: Gift System in Ancient India (New
Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers, 1987).
(29) See Melford Spiro, Buddhism and Society (New York:
Harper & Row, Publishers, 1970); Winston L. King, In the Hope of
Nibbana (LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1964). Spiro and King, while
admiring many of the personal qualities of Buddhist laypeople, tend to
diminish their moral achievements as self-regarding, because lay
Buddhists link good deeds and good character with favorable rebirths.
Scholars from Christian cultures that have given the highest moral
value to self-sacrificing altruism, agape, are not likely to regard
the Buddha's injunction, to avoid the extremes of self-indulgence and
self-mortification, as the most heroic spiritual advice.
(30) Some scholars believe King and Spiro make too sharp a
distinction between layperson and monk, between kamma-motives and
Nibbāna-motives, in Theravāda Buddhism. See, Harvey B. Aronson, "The
Relationship of the Karmic to the Nirvanic in Theravada Buddhism," The
Journal of Religious Ethics, Vol. 7 No. 1 (Spring 1979), 28-36; Donald
K. Swearer, "Bhikkhu Buddhadasa on Ethics and Society," The Journal of
Religious Ethics, Vol. 7 No. 1 (Spring 1979), 54-64. Southwold makes
his argument against this "elitist" and "modernist" interpretation of
a dualistic Buddhism the center of his work, Buddhism in Life. See
also, Damien Keown, The Nature of Buddhist Ethics, 83-105.
(31) Robert A. Thurman, trans., The Holy Teaching of
Vimalakīrti (London: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1976).
(32) This self-concept gives trouble to ethical systems,
like Kant's, and social-political traditions, like Western liberalism
(of progressive or conservative varieties), that function in terms of
rights-claims, human rights, etc. Buddhist ethics, insofar as it is
grounded in the processional, ecological self-in-community, and
articulated teleologically in terms of the specific pāramitās and
their cultivation, must be in tension with Western tradition on this
issue, so long as Western ethics and legal structures are primarily
designed to serve individual and corporate property interests. This is
not to claim that Buddhist ethics overlooks or radically discounts
individual human rights. The origins of Buddhism clearly reflect a
vision of human life that is prejudiced toward individual release from
social, as well as psychic, oppression of the human spirit. Buddhist
ethics supports democracy and human rights protection as a preferable
arrangement of social, legal, and religious tolerance. However,
Buddhist ethics views such tolerance and protection as only two of the
conditions for a good human life.
(33) See Joanna Macy, "The Ecological Self: Postmodern
Ground for Right Action," Sacred Interconnections, ed. David Ray
Griffin (Albany: State University Press of New York, 1990), 35-48.
(34) David E. Shaner develops the Japanese Buddhist
connection between cultivation of character and a "biophilic"
experience of nature in an excellent article, "The Japanese Experience
of Nature," Nature in Asian Traditions of Thought, ed. J. Baird
Callicott and Roger T. Ames (Albany: State University of New York
Press, 1989),163-82.
(35) See Shaner's review of recent biographies of the
Buddha, in which he discusses the nature and limits of Buddhist
hagiography; David E. Shaner, "Biographies of the Buddha" Philosophy
East and West 37 (July 1987), 306-22.
(36) Helen Tworkov's Zen in America: Profiles of Five
Teachers discusses moral concerns in connection with the behavior of
some American Zen teachers, but avoids using the words "moral" and
"ethical" and makes little use of Buddhist moral tradition to clarify
the concerns discussed. Tworkov, Zen in America (San Francisco: North
Point Press, 1989). Sandy Boucher reports moral concerns of many
American women growing out of their experiences in American Buddhist
centers; Boucher, Turning the Wheel: American Women Creating the New
Buddhism.
(37) Frank Kirkpatrick and I have ventured a comparative
philosophical discussion of Buddhist and Christian models of community
in our "Mutual/Personal Community: Buddhist and Christian Models"
(unpublished manuscript, 1990). See Kirkpatrick's Together Bound: God,
History, and the Religious Community (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1994).
(38) See, for example, Alasdair MacIntyre's much referred
to chapter, "The Virtues, The Unity of a Human Life and the Concept of
a Tradition," in After Virtue. His emphasis on the "narrative" quality
of life is not common to all virtue theorists. The Buddhist notion of
"narrative" is, I presume, sufficiently different from the Christian
notion to offer a useful test of MacIntyre's claims. For example, is
the story of Jesus' life, death and resurrection more "plausible"
MacIntyre's criterion) than the story of Siddhārtha Gautama? Copyright
1994, http://jbe.gold.ac.uk/index.html
--o0o--
|