"Cutting the Roots of Virtue:"
Tsongkhapa on the Results of Anger
By Daniel Cozort
Assistant Professor of Religion, Dickinson College
ISSN 1076-9005, Volume 2 1995
---o0o---
Abstract:
Anger is the most powerful of the kle"sas that not only
"plant seeds" for suffering but also "cut the roots of virtue" for
periods of up to a thousand aeons per instance. This article examines
and assesses the exegesis by Tsongkhapa, founder of the Tibetan
Gelukba order, of Indian sources on the topic of anger. It argues that
despite Tsongkhapa's many careful qualifications he may not be
successful in avoiding the conclusion that if the sūtras are to be
accepted literally, there almost certainly will be persons for whom
liberation from saṃsāra
is precluded.
INTRODUCTION
Among the six root afflictive emotions (nyon mongs, kle"sa)
identified in the Buddhist Abhidharma literature as the causes for
episodes or entire lifetimes of suffering, anger (Tibetan: khong khro,
Sanskrit: pratigha) holds a singular place. It is one of a few mental
states (1) that not only establish "seeds" or "roots" of nonvirtue,
but also nullify the seeds or roots of individual virtue planted by
exemplary actions such as giving and patience. Among these states,
anger is uniquely destructive. The Mañju"srīvikrīḍita
Sūtra warns that a single moment of anger can result in a person's
loss of a hundred aeons of virtue.(2) "Sāntideva, the ninth century
author of the greatly influential Bodhisattvacaryāvatāra multiplies
this dire warning tenfold (chapter 6, verse 1): anger wipes out not
just a hundred, but a thousand aeons of virtue.
Since most people lose their tempers with dismaying
frequency, it seems reasonable to wonder how, from a Buddhist
perspective, it is possible simultaneously to contend that a mere
outburst can have such an extraordinarily negative effect and to
assert, as Mahāyāna Buddhists generally do, that all sentient beings
will gain merit sufficient to attain liberation. It appears that
apologists for the Mahāyāna tradition have a heavy burden--they must
either interpret statements about anger's effect on the stores of
virtue as gross exaggerations spun out as a matter of "skill in means"
(thabs la mkhas pa, upāya-kau"salya), delimit the range of persons to
whom they are said to apply, or indicate ways in which anger's effects
can be ameliorated.
Tsongkhapa Losang Drakba (3) (tsong kha pa blo bzang grags
pa, 1357-1419), founder of the Tibetan Gelukba (dge lugs pa) order,
uses the latter two routes in his extensive analysis of anger. I will
examine portions of his Great Exposition of the Stages of the Path
(completed in 1402) and his Illumination of the Thought, Extensive
Explanation of (Candrakīrti's) Madhyamakāvatāra (1418) where
Tsongkhapa meticulously scrutinizes the Indian sources. In these works
he assesses the importance of the status of the recipient of anger and
attempts to explain what precisely it does and does not mean to "cut
the roots" of virtue for the incredible spans indicated in the Indian
sources.(4) In the process, he manages to limit significantly the
scope of the Indian sources, explaining that they refer only to anger
at bodhisattvas and that "cutting" the roots of virtue means something
far less than "destroying." However, it is not clear that, in the end,
Tsongkhapa has succeeded in demonstrating that anger does not, at
least in some cases, prevent salvation.
QUANTIFYING THE PENALTY FOR ANGER
Although clearly the Buddha regarded anger as a massively
destructive force, sūtra sources that quantify its effect are
noticeably scarce. Tsongkhapa cites the Upāliparipṛcchā
Sūtra, the Mañju"srīvikrīḍita
Sūtra, and the Sañchayagāthāprajñāpāramitā Sūtra. The Upāliparipṛcchā
Sūtra (5) warns that there is no greater cause for elimination of the
roots of virtue "than when one spiritual adept (brahmacārya) abuses
another," but it does not specify how great that loss might be. For
that, the locus classicus appears to be the aforementioned
Mañju"srīvikrīḍita
Sūtra which warns that one may lose a hundred aeons of virtue in a
moment of anger. Candrakīrti (7th cent.), the Mādhyamaka interpreter
through whom Tsongkhapa views nearly all important matters of Buddhist
doctrine, possibly basing his estimate on this source, also states
that anger destroys a hundred aeons of virtue (Madhyamakāvatāra 3.33):
- Therefore, anger toward a Conqueror Child
- Destroys the virtue arisen from giving and ethical
discipline,
- Accumulated over a hundred aeons, in a moment.
Candrakīrti clarifies the sūtra by indicating that
hundred-aeon anger is directed at a "Conqueror Child," or
bodhisattva--a person who, for Tsongkhapa, has an aspiration to
Buddhahood both altruistic and spontaneous (but who is not necessarily
someone who has amassed significant amounts of merit or wisdom). This,
of course, greatly reduces the probable instances of hundred-aeon
anger by an ordinary person. Tsongkhapa also cites "Sāntideva,(6) who
without specifying the recipient of anger, says (Bodhisattvacaryāvatāra
6.1):
- Whatever good deeds [you have done],
- Collected over a thousand aeons,
- Such as giving and homage to the Ones Gone Thus
- Are destroyed in one [moment of] anger.
Aware that Candrakīrti has specified that the recipient of
hundred- aeon anger is a bodhisattva, he surmises that the recipient
of the thousand-aeon anger mentioned by "Sāntideva must also be a
bodhisattva and, moreover, that the angry person must be a non-
bodhisattva.(7) If this is what "Sāntideva meant, we might suppose
that a thousand-aeon penalty would be a rather rare occurrence. Given
a bodhisattva's generally benign behavior, presumably a bodhisattva
would rarely commit acts that would spur the wrath of others.(8)
Continuing with this line of reasoning, Tsongkhapa
concludes that if the supreme penalty for anger involves a
non-bodhisattva's anger with a bodhisattva, then Candrakīrti's
reference to a lesser penalty that also involves anger with a
bodhisattva can only mean that one bodhisattva is angry with another.
It is surprising to learn that bodhisattvas ever get angry, since they
are, for Tsongkhapa, persons always able to rouse their bodhicitta,
the altruistic aspiration to Buddhahood. However, although bodhicitta
can arise spontaneously, it is not continuously present in non-buddhas,
and at least some bodhisattvas are susceptible to anger for nearly all
of a period of "uncountable" aeons. This is the length of the paths of
"accumulation" (tshogs lam, saṃbhāramārga)
and "preparation" (sbyor lam, prayogamārga), the first two of the five
paths concluding in Buddhahood.(9) Anger is not precluded until one is
well into the path of preparation, the second part of which is called
"peak" (rtse mo, mūrdhan) because it is the end of the period in which
one can generate anger that will sever the roots of virtue. At least
one contemporary scholar says that a bodhisattva may become angry even
after that point, but the anger is weaker than the anger to which the
quotations refer and will not sever the roots of virtue.(10)
Tsongkhapa is very specific about the consequences of
being an angry bodhisattva. A mature bodhisattva who is angered by one
who is lesser (11) loses a hundred aeons of virtue; on the other hand,
a bodhisattva angry with a greater one loses an aeon of virtue for
each instant of the anger's duration. In the latter case, Tsongkhapa
has a source in the Sañchayagāthāprajñāpāramitā Sūtra, which states:
(12)
- If a bodhisattva who has not been prophesied
- Angers and disputes with another who has so been,
- He must bear the armor from the beginning for as many
- Aeons as the times his mind was imbued with hatred.
Tsongkhapa interprets this to mean that a bodhisattva's
anger with one who has received the prophesy of Buddhahood from a
Buddha will impede the former's progress for many aeons. For example,
someone about to progress from the path of accumulation to the path of
preparation would be set back for as many aeons as there were instants
of anger. Presumably the number of instants would swiftly rise above
one hundred, since anger has more serious consequences for lower
persons than high ones and otherwise the greater bodhisattva would pay
a higher price than a lesser.
However rare or common angry bodhisattvas might be, they
incur lesser "penalties" for anger than do the rest of us. A
bodhisattva's anger with a non-bodhisattva would entail a penalty far
less than a hundred aeons. Tsongkhapa explicitly asserts that "Only a
bodhisattva is an object of anger that destroys roots of virtue
accumulated over a hundred or a thousand aeons." (13)
According to Tsongkhapa, it does not matter whether one
knows as a bodhisattva the person with whom one is angry. This is
unexpected. Tibetan discussions of karma virtually always classify
correct identification of the recipient of an action as a primary
consideration in the determination of a specific act's weightiness. It
is of lesser consequence, for instance, to shoot a gun at a coiled
rope in the corner of a darkened room that one believes mistakenly to
be a snake than to shoot at an actual snake. However, perhaps
Tsongkhapa would answer that even if one does not realize that the
person at whom one is angry is an actual bodhisattva, one certainly
would have had experience of that person's compassion; one therefore
would have correctly identified the fundamental character of the
person even if one did not realize that the person merited the title
"bodhisattva." If so, it would support the view of the contemporary
Gelukba scholar, Geshe Kelsang Gyatso (14) , who contends that anger
toward anyone who has shown one great kindness is a source of
"limitless destruction of merit." To become angry even at an equal, he
continues, may cost roots of virtue collected over many lifetimes. To
speculate, perhaps this is because anger mixed with ingratitude
contributes to pride and other kle"sas. This modern interpretation
seems consonant with the thrust of the Indian sources.
Whoever is the recipient of one's anger, clearly anger is
considered an immensely negative force. We would not be surprised to
learn that anger could result in rebirth in a hell for thousands of
years or that it might give one who had an otherwise fortunate birth
an ugly countenance. But anger is far worse. What makes anger
different from most other nonvirtues is that it not only contributes
to the store of causes for miserable future experiences but also
affects the store of causes for fortunate experiences.
CUTTING VIRTUE'S ROOTS
Tsongkhapa calls the principal effect of anger "cutting"
the "roots of virtue" (dge rtsa, ku"sulamūla).(15) Ways to cultivate
and "plant" roots of virtue were a major concern in early Buddhism, as
Robert Buswell has recently shown.(16) For instance, roots of virtue
are a major topic in the Abhidharmamahāvibhāṣā
(second cent.), the document from which comes the name of the Vaibhāṣika
school that, according to Tibetan doxographers, is one of the two
principal Hīnayāna systems. Subsequent theoreticians of karma retained
the horticultural metaphor but switched to the image of "seeds" rather
than roots; Tsongkhapa treats "roots" and "seeds" as synonymous terms.
Both refer to the establishment in an individual continūm of a
potential for future effects. Both virtuous intentional actions and
nonvirtuous intentional actions infuse an individual continūm with
potentials. The nature of these potentials --are they physical?
mental? neither?--has long been debated in Buddhist scholasticism.
Again, the Indian texts seem to warn clearly and
unambiguously that even a moment of anger can wipe out the virtue one
has accumulated over the course of aeons. What else might it mean to
"destroy" (bcom) virtue "from the roots?" When a plant's roots are
cut, it usually dies. Alternately, when its seeds are destroyed it can
no longer bear fruit. However, some plants, such as the sweet potato,
do not die when their roots are cut; they lie dormant until the
conditions exist for their regeneration, or they slowly produce new
root systems. Tsongkhapa, it seems, considers virtue to be a sweet
potato. He explains that when anger "cuts" virtue's "roots," it is not
destroyed, although aeons will roll on before it again becomes capable
of producing the sweet fruit of a pleasant rebirth. Therefore,
"destruction of the roots of virtue" (dge pa'i rtsa la bcom pa) is not
equivalent to "totally cutting the roots of virtue" (dge pa'i rtsa ba
kun tu chad pa, samucchinnaku"salamūla) which for some early Buddhists
meant a permanent disbarment from liberation.(17)
This is the picture that emerges from Tsongkhapa's
reflections in the "Patience" chapter of his Lam rim chen mo. It
arises as he addresses himself to certain unnamed scholars, apparently
(18) the followers of Bud"on (bu ston, 1290-1364), the prolific
scholar of the Sagya (sa skya) sect whose influential works were still
reverberating when Tsongkhapa began his Buddhist studies. He affirms
Bud"on's basic interpretation: despite the presence in the Indian
sources of apparently unambiguous language such as "destruction" or
"elimination," the "seeds" (sa bon, bīja) established by virtuous
actions are certainly not destroyed by negative emotions such as
anger; they are merely incapacitated. They cannot be destroyed by
anger because only wisdom--consciousnesses at the level of the path of
seeing (mthong lam, dar"sanamārga) and above--can eliminate karmic
seeds. That is, until one has experienced emptiness (stong pa nyid, "sūnyatā)
mystically--without any dualities, without conceptuality--liberation
from any sort of karma and its results is impossible. Hence, the
language of the Indian texts is not literal, but must be interpreted
in the following way: because the seeds of virtue cannot reach
fruition, for the angry person it is as though the roots of virtue
were destroyed.
Although it is not a question Tsongkhapa addresses
explicitly, we can see that by interpreting "cutting" as something
less than destruction, Tibetan exegetes seek to avoid a serious
challenge to the Mahāyāna doctrine of universal salvation (namely,
that all sentient beings will eventually reach Buddhahood). If anger
can be so potent, and as we know too well ourselves, occur so
frequently, then certainly how could they ever have fortunate rebirths
in which to make progress toward Buddhahood? Asa"nga (fourth cent.),
in his Abhidharmasamuccaya, asks just this question.(19) He makes a
distinction between "roots" and "seeds" of virtue and nonvirtue such
that it might be possible for someone to have lost roots but not seeds
and therefore retain the possibility of future regeneration of the
roots of virtue. However, he contends that there are some among those
whose roots of virtue are eradicated who also have no seeds of virtue
and therefore have no "dharma of parinirvāṇa."
They make saṃsāra
truly endless, for they themselves will never escape it. Tsongkhapa
makes no distinction like Asa"nga's between "roots" and "seeds" and
does not admit the possibility that some are doomed to endless saṃsāra.
He appears to think that since the roots of virtue can be regenerated,
and since, moreover (as we will see below), their period of dormancy
can be abbreviated by the application of proper antidotes to the
poison that has deadened them, no such result need be entailed. As I
state later, it is not clear that his explanation succeeds.
Although Tsongkhapa agrees with Bud"on and his followers
that the roots of virtue continue to exist despite anger, he disagrees
with them over whether this will entail adverse consequences. The
problem, they think, with asserting that virtue might still exist
despite having been "cut" is that it might then seem to follow that if
certain precise conditions were to occur, virtue's seeds might yet
sprout; therefore, anger would not actually have had a deleterious
effect on virtue. For example, if virtue continued to exist, could not
a wayward monk whose temper too often bested him somehow still
experience the effects of past virtue? Tsongkhapa's response falls
under several heads.
SEEDS CAN EXIST WITHOUT RIPENING
In the first place, Tsongkhapa wishes to establish that
karmic seeds can exist without ripening even in the presence of
conditions that ordinarily would cause them to "sprout." He relies on
Bhāvaviveka's (sixth cent.) Madhyamakahṛdayavṛttitarkajvālā
to assert that, for example, even an "ordinary" person (one who has
not had the mystical experience of emptiness) can use the "four
opponent powers"--remorse, restraint, the cultivation of specific
"antidotes," and cultivating bodhicitta (20) -- to suppress the
issuance of the effects of nonvirtue. One might regret a harsh
utterance, pledge not to repeat the behavior, cultivate
loving-kindness, and so forth. Just as anger cannot destroy the seeds
of virtue, so the four powers do not destroy the seeds of non-virtue,
but they do prevent their unpleasant effects from being issued.(21)
This suppression of the maturation of negative karmic seeds is
commonly called "purification," which one might incorrectly assume
entailed complete destruction or elimination, but as we have seen can
mean only temporary incapacitation.
Another of Tsongkhapa's examples involves a far more
advanced person who has attained the path of preparation, that level
at which, according to Tsongkhapa, there has been an inferential
understanding of emptiness.(22) For such a person, the attainment of a
higher path consciousness ensures that even the presence of what
ordinarily would be proper ripening conditions will still not lead to
the maturation of those seeds of non-virtue that could ripen as wrong
views (log lta, mithyāḍṛṣṭi)
or birth in the miserable realms of animals, hungry ghosts, and
hell-beings. As in the previous instance, although the seeds cannot
yet be destroyed, they can be incapacitated.
Indeed, all "heavy" karma, the sort that results in
particularly fortunate or miserable birth, suppresses the issuance of
effects that are contrary to it. For instance, a hell-being never
experiences pleasure, nor does a god experience pain (until, after
vast stretches of time, his or her birth-impelling karma approaches
exhaustion). Therefore, in Buddhist cosmology, the incapacitation of
seeds of nonvirtue or virtue is a common occurrence.(23)
Tsongkhapa's final example is not as obvious as the
others. Among seeds that exist without ripening are those that have
already ripened, yet continue to exist. Commenting (in Illumination)
on a passage in the Akṣayamatinirde"sa
Sūtra that compares virtue to a drop of water placed in the ocean,
remaining as long as the ocean endures, Tsongkhapa says,(24) "Virtuous
roots are not consumed through the emergence of their effects;
however, it is not the case that anger does not consume them." In
Great Exposition he says, "Even with regard to virtuous and
nonvirtuous actions that have ceased upon issuing their own
maturation, there has not been an elimination of their seeds."(25) In
brief, he says that actions can cause effects without being "used up."
How could "ripened seeds" continue to have any kind of
existence? We must recall that seeds established by virtue (or
nonvirtue) cannot be destroyed by anything other than wisdom of the
path of seeing or above; therefore, they are not destroyed even if
their effects have already issued forth. This point is, perhaps,
counter-intuitive: once a seed has produced its effect, what sense can
be made of saying that it continues to exist? It is as though one were
to say that despite the fact that a seed had developed into a tree,
the seed continued to exist (although it could not, of course, produce
yet another tree). I think, however, that Tsongkhapa's point is
considerably more subtle. He expands upon it in Illumination,
commenting on Candrakīrti's statement in Madhyāmakāvatāra (6.33) that:
- Because a sprout is not [inherently](26) other than its
seed,
- At the time of a sprout, the seed has not been
destroyed.
- However, because they are not the same
- It is not said that at the time of a sprout its seed
exists.
Tsongkhapa comments (27) In the [non-Prāsa"ngika] systems,
they think: "When a thing such as a sprout has disintegrated,
everything that is part of the sprout is obliterated." Since one does
not get any other thing that is different from a sprout, such as a
pot, they assert that disintegratedness (zhig pa) is utterly not a
thing. In the [Prāsa"ngika] system, for example, one cannot designate
(1) Upagupta's individual five aggregates (phung bo, skandha), (2)
their collection, or (3) that which is a different entity from those
two as an illustration of Upagupta, and Upagupta is also unsuitable to
be an illustration of those three. However, it is not contradictory
that despite that, what is designated as Upagupta in dependence on his
aggregates is a thing. Similarly, even though disintegratedness also
cannot be an illustration of either the thing (dngos po, bhāva) that
has been destroyed or anything that is the same type as that, it is a
thing because it is produced in dependence on a thing that has been
destroyed.
In Tsongkhapa's view, karmic "seeds" are neither physical
presences nor even mental phenomena that persist over time. Then, what
are they? They are "disintegratednesses" (zhig pa, naṣṭa--there
is no graceful English term). Because all impermanent phenomena
disintegrate moment-by-moment, when an action disintegrates, its state
of having disintegrated--its disintegratedness--arises. It too,
disintegrates, giving rise to the "disintegratedness of the
disintegratedness" of the action, and so on, until a fruition occurs.
Hence, "seed" really refers to the present moment of "disintegratedness"
of an original action. Asserting that "disintegratedness" is a
functioning entity but denying that it is substantially existent
allows Tsongkhapa to avoid either the absurdity of saying that karma
persists unchanged or of proposing a substantially existent entity
like the Vaibhāṣika
"acquisition" (thob, prāpti) to account for the continuing link
between a mind-stream and a karma.(28)
Based on his understanding of Prāsa"ngika philosophy,
Tsongkhapa describes all phenomena as mere imputations designated in
dependence on certain bases. In his example, a man named Upagupta is
not identical with the body and mind in dependence on which "Upagupta"
is designated. This is Upagupta's mode of existence because he is
empty of inherent existence (rang bzhin gyis grub pa, svabhāvasiddhi).
Nevertheless, Upagupta exists. Similarly, says Tsongkhapa, the "disintegratedness"
of a virtuous action exists upon the action's disintegration. Although
there is nothing to which one can point that is the "disintegratedness"
(just as there was nothing to which one could point which was Upagupta),
nevertheless there is a basis--the disintegrated action--in dependence
on which "disintegratedness" can be designated (just as there is a
basis--a body and mind--in dependence on which "Upagupta" can be
designated).
The consequence of this is that Tsongkhapa feels that it
is possible to assert that even when an actions's fruition has been
experienced, the action's disintegratedness, which functions as its
"seed," does not cease. Of course, how could "disintegratedness" ever
cease to exist? Once something has disintegrated, it will always be
true that it has disintegrated. Thus, there is no way that anger could
destroy the seeds of virtuous actions.(29) (It may also be that this
manner of explaining the persistence of virtue's "seeds" even when
virtue has been "ripened" has to do with denying that the accumulation
of merit is a "zero-sum game." That is, although virtue might ripen in
fortunate rebirths, it continues to "count" toward the store of merit
that comprises half -- the other half being the store of wisdom -- of
the requisite for Buddhahood.) (30)
ONE CAN BE VIRTUOUS WITHOUT HAVING ROOTS
Tsongkhapa explicitly argues that not only does anger not
really destroy the roots of virtue, it does not preclude the
performance of virtuous acts. That is, even though one cannot
experience the effect of previous virtuous actions during the period
in which virtuous roots have been incapacitated, one's predispositions
to perform virtuous acts have not necessarily been eliminated.
We might have expected the opposite, namely, that one
result of the incapacitation of virtue would be a neutralization or
reversal of its "habitual" effect, the establishment of propensities
for further virtuous action.(31) Apparently Tsongkhapa feels that
although the seeds are incapacitated, the habits are not necessarily
broken. This makes sense because even angry persons may have had much
conditioning to predispose them to virtuous behavior. Certainly this
would be true in the cases of the bodhisattvas who become angry with
each other or with common beings. It would contradict what we observe
daily to maintain that a moment of anger dramatically and permanently
alters an otherwise balanced or even benevolent personality.
If, then, one can accumulate more virtue, does this mean
that there are "fresh seeds" that might ripen as fortunate rebirth or
pleasant experiences? If so, does this not considerably reduce the
negative effect of anger? Since this would otherwise constitute a
major loophole in Tsongkhapa's formulation, we can perhaps presume
that these seeds, too, are incapacitated by anger. This assumption is
consistent with the basic thrust of Tsongkhapa's interpretation of the
meaning of "cutting the roots of virtue," since it looks forward
toward aeons in which there will be no ripening of the seeds of virtue
rather than looking backwards at so many aeons of virtue ruined. Of
course, it leads to the apparent paradox that the stores of virtue may
be increased during the same period in which virtue's roots are "cut"
and raises questions such as: if new roots of virtue are produced --
and incapacitated -- does this mean that some dormant "older" roots
are activated? In other words, does anger affect a certain quantity of
virtuous roots?
VIRTUE THAT IS CUT ONLY PARTIALLY
Besides tempering what the Indian texts say about the
existence of virtue and affirming the possibility of its performance,
Tsongkhapa also distinguishes between degrees of anger, only the worst
of which truly "cuts" the roots of virtue. Thus, he appears to think
that although in general, the seeds of virtue cannot ripen, there may
be exceptions. He says: (32) The overcoming of a virtue does not mean
that a virtue in one's continūm ceases to exist after one generates
anger; rather, anger harms the virtue's capacity to issue forth an
effect. The extent to which later fruition is harmed accords with the
amount of harm done, causing a small, middling, or great
extinguishment of virtue as explained above.
Tsongkhapa is referring to the Upāliparipṛcchā
Sūtra, which said: Upāli, I have not seen such a drawing of a wound or
maiming as when a trainee in the pure life (brahmacārya) abuses
[another] trainee in the pure life. Upāli, then those great roots of
virtue become diminished, thoroughly reduced, and eliminated. Upāli,
if you would not try to attack with your mind things such as burning
logs, what can we say about a body with consciousness?
Tsongkhapa interprets "diminished," "reduced," and
"eliminated" respectively as small, middling, and complete
elimination. That is, he argues that although it is true that anger
cuts the roots of virtue, it may do so only partially. It is not clear
whether this means that in "small" or "middling" eliminations only
some roots of virtue are touched or whether it means that all roots of
virtue are diminished significantly, so that only partial fortunate
results are possible.
In short, Tsongkhapa argues that although the Indian texts
warn of draconian consequences to even a moment of anger--the loss of
a thousand aeons of virtue, for instance--this really means, in most
cases, that there is a partial incapacitation of that virtue for a
long future period. The result is that some of the seeds of virtue
might actually ripen as a good body with good resources, etc., and
because of this one could probably continue to make progress as a
bodhisattva on the paths to Buddhahood. However, one's progress will
be slow. A novice bodhisattva's anger at a mature bodhisattva, for
instance, will not de-commission her, but it will impede her
development. Therefore, "cut" not only means just "incapacitation" but
also just "mostly incapacitated." Perhaps anger incapacitates those
roots of virtue that would have ripened as lifetimes with superb
conditions for the study of Dharma, enabling only those roots of
virtue that could ripen as lifetimes or circumstances that are
relatively mediocre.
CONTRADICTIONS, APPARENT AND REAL
According to Tsongkhapa's own reckoning, the journey over
the paths to Buddhahood requires no less than three periods of
"countless" great aeons. In a sense, then, a moment of anger amounts
to no more than a stumble on the path. On the other hand, who gets
angry only once in a great while -- like a thousand aeons, for
instance? Even with Tsongkhapa's modifications, it seems likely that
an ordinary person would have little virtue not incapacitated by
anger. The most serious problem with any of the accounts of the effect
of anger, then, is that they seem to leave open the possibility that
there might be persons who would be the karmic equivalent of
indentured servants, unable ever to be born into a body from which
they could seek liberation. This would contradict a deeply held dogma
about the possibility of universal salvation, which Tsongkhapa
supports.(33) A single lifetime's episode of anger (particularly if
that life is spent largely being jealous of one or more real
bodhisattvas) could easily dig a hole so deep that even innumerable
aeons seem too brief to permit escape. For, one of the principal
reasons why vice is vicious is that it impels one into life after
suffering life in which anger, among other negative emotions, is the
norm rather than the exception. The Tibetan tradition uses a famous
analogy to saṃsāra
which compares the chances of being born as a human who can hear the
Dharma to the odds that a blind sea turtle, surfacing only once in a
hundred years, will stick its head through a golden yoke floating on a
vast ocean. Adding multiple-aeon calculations on anger is like
changing the setting of this scenario to outer space. What odds
remain? In short, Tsongkhapa's efforts at moderation notwithstanding,
the Indian sources seem to lead to an untenable conclusion.
Second, an apparent self-contradiction in Tsongkhapa's
interpretation is that he himself maintains that regarding the roots
of virtue, "cut" cannot be equated with "delay" or else there would be
no great difference between anger and other negative emotions such as
jealousy or gossiping, which also can delay the issuance of the
effects of virtue. He says: "The mere temporary postponement of
maturation is not appropriate to be the meaning of destroying the
roots of virtue; otherwise, all the nonvirtuous actions that have
power would have to be set forth as destroyers of the roots of
virtue."(34) Based on our analysis, it is difficult to see how his
understanding of the destruction of roots of virtue amounts to
anything other than delay, since anger, though much more potent than
any of these other kle"sas, seems to be different only by degree.
However, Tsongkhapa focuses upon the way in which the other kle"sas
cause a delay: (35)
The virtuous or nonvirtuous actions that have matured
earlier temporarily stop the opportunity for the maturation of other
actions; however, merely those [earlier maturations] cannot destroy
virtue or nonvirtue and that is not set forth [in scripture as the
meaning of "cut" the roots of virtue].
The fruition of the seeds of any virtuous or nonvirtuous
action can result in a birth that prevents the maturation of seeds of
its opposite. For instance, a seed established by nonvirtue might
ripen as a birth in one of the hells. Because such a life is devoid of
pleasure, seeds formerly established by virtue would lack the
necessary conditions for their maturation. These seeds would not have
been rendered ineffective in exactly the same way that anger renders
seeds ineffective; they would not have been "cut" or "scorched" or
"withered" or otherwise directly neutralized. They would be like
patrons in line for a film who do not know that around the corner,
near the box office, others are cutting in. But what difference does
it make that anger and pride, for instance, operate differently? In
practice, the result is the same.
OTHER QUESTIONS
By focussing on the narrow issue of how and to what degree
anger affects the stores of virtue, we have not yet asked several
obvious questions that probably should be raised before leaving the
topic. First, why is anger seen to be so incredibly destructive? There
is no other religious tradition that approaches Buddhism in its
negative assessment of the consequences of a moment's angry outburst.
What is special about anger for Buddhists?
Let us look at Tsongkhapa's arguments against anger (in
which he follows the lead of "Sāntideva's Bodhisattvacaryāvatāra).(36)
(1) Anger against others is irrational because others lack autonomy.
They are helpless against their own conditioning, which leads them to
commit acts that provoke us to anger. It is obvious that they lack
autonomy because even though they themselves want happiness, they
commit acts that lead to suffering. (2) Similarly, if one thinks that
others are inherently annoying, they cannot rationally be blamed,
since they are merely doing what is their nature. (3) If, on the other
hand, their annoying qualities are not inherent, then those qualities
are a merely adventitious product of conditioning and should not be
held against them. (4) The provocative person is only indirectly
responsible for annoyance; he or she is being used by hate in the same
way that a person uses a stick. One should oppose the annoyance, not
the person ("love the sinner, hate the sin"). (5) Whatever makes one
angry is the result of one's own past actions. Annoying persons are
nothing other than the agents of one's own previous misdeeds. And (6)
only a provocative person gives one the opportunity to amass merit
that can be helpful for spiritual progress. Therefore, one ought to be
grateful for the provocation.
Note that focus is on what happens to a person who gets
angry, not on the immediate consequences to the recipient of the
anger. In other words, Tsongkhapa does not argue that anger ought to
be avoided because it leads to violence against others or because it
tends to provoke the recipient of one's anger into an equally angry
state. These would be legitimate arguments, but Tsongkhapa's concern
is for the mental state of the person who gets angry. He wishes to
convince us that anger is simply irrational and that forbearance is
beneficial, not that anger is wrong because it leads to physical or
verbal acts (as he might argue if, for instance, he were addressing
the faults of intoxication). It is a reminder that karma is primarily
about intention (sems pa, cetanā), not act.
What is noteworthy about these arguments is that most of
them revolve around the angry person's assumption of autonomy with
respect to a provocateur--around the sort of ignorance that Buddhists
identify as the "root of saṃsāra."
To be angry with someone implies that one falsely imputes to that
person an autonomous self, and the dynamics of anger serve to reify
that misconception. Tsongkhapa also demonstrates that anger involves
ignorance about oneself, for it indicates that one does not understand
that harms, real or imagined, arise only in dependence upon one's own
continūm.(37) Because anger reifies ignorance, it is strongly contrary
not only to the development of wisdom but also to the development of
compassion, which grows only where the distinction of self-and-other
has been weakened. Perhaps, then, anger is felt to be in a different
class than other nonvirtues because even more than desire, etc., it
solidifies that most vicious of all vices, ignorance? That is why
anger joins ignorance and desire to comprise the "three poisons"
functioning as the hub of the wheel of saṃsāra.
Moving to a second question, why do Buddhists say that
anger affects virtue instead of simply saying that anger is a
nonvirtuous act that carries tremendous potential for future
suffering? Why place anger (and a few other nonvirtues, as described
below) in a different category than any other act? Perhaps the answer
is that anger does not merely set in motion a future retribution and
habituate the one it grasps to further outbursts; it creates a mood,
or is one, which undermines positive thoughts and actions. It would
not be sufficient on the plane of ordinary experience to describe
anger's effect only in terms of future negative effects. We would
surely also want to add that anger diminishes positive movement.
Thinking homologically, it must seem necessary in karmic theory to
claim that anger produces not only roots of nonvirtue but affects the
roots of virtue as well.
This is equally true of weighty virtues, such as giving.
They establish roots or seeds for future pleasant lives or
experiences, but they also "purify" nonvirtues (as we saw above when
we considered the four powers that can temporarily nullify nonvirtues).
The language of cleaning, rather than that of destruction, is used;
for instance, we are not told that generosity "cuts the roots of
nonvirtue." With virtues, what Buddhist teachers emphasize are ways in
which the fruition of the virtues will enhance the attainment of
liberation for oneself and others.(38)
Finally, one question that might be raised with regard to
the purification of nonvirtue is what consequence this might have for
virtue. We have seen that according to Tsongkhapa, anger can be
nullified by the four opponent powers of remorse, restraint, etc.(39)
But if anger is nullified by remorse, etc., is its nullification of
virtue similarly cancelled? Are the roots of virtue then freed? Or
does one just establish roots of liberation? Tsongkhapa, commenting in
Great Exposition on Bhāvaviveka's statement that even though there is
purification by the four powers, there is no destruction of seeds,
concludes that "even though your accumulation of sins is washed away
through purification by the four powers, this does not contradict the
fact that you are slow to produce higher paths."(40) In Illumination
he is even more explicit; referring to the Sarvavaidalyasaṃgraha
Sūtra, he says: (41) If one abandons the doctrine as set forth in the
sūtra but confesses the fault three times daily for seven years, the
fruition of that deed is purified, but even at the fastest ten aeons
are necessary to attain endurance [i.e., to progress to the next
path]. Thus, even though confession and restraint in many ways does
not restore a path that has become slower, it will purify experience
of the fruition.
In other words, the purification of nonvirtues such as
anger does not undo its devastating effect on virtue. "Purification"
prevents the issuance of unpleasant effects, but does not rehabilitate
good seeds gone bad.
SUMMARY
Anger, identified along with ignorance and desire as a
"poison" that generates saṃsāra,
is singled out by Tsongkhapa as a particularly destructive emotion. It
is founded on ignorance and reifies it. It not only establishes
potentials for future occasions of suffering and habituates its
subject to react similarly in future provocative circumstances, but
also has a considerable impact on the store of previously accomplished
virtue. The magnitude of its effect on virtue is dependent on (1) the
degree of anger, (2) the status of the person with toward whom it is
directed, (3) the status of the person who is angry, and (4) whether
it is "purified" by the four opponent powers. To expand briefly on
these points:
1- Anger has "small," "middling," and "great" forms. Only
anger that is of "great" intensity can "cut the roots" of virtue.
While lesser instances presumably can produce painful effects, they do
not also affect the ripening of virtue.
2- Anger is most destructive that is directed toward
persons who display great compassion. Therefore, anger with buddhas
and mature bodhisattvas is worst, anger with lesser bodhisattvas next
worst, anger with persons who have shown one great kindness next
worst, and so on.
3- Conversely, the higher a person's status, the less
damaging are his or her instances of anger. If a mature bodhisattva
were ever angry, the anger would have only minor consequences; an
ordinary person's anger with a buddha or mature bodhisattva, on the
other hand, can result in the cutting of the roots of virtue for a
thousand aeons.
4- Anger that is not addressed will fester and fulfill its
potential for destruction. Remorse, etc., can nullify the painful
effects of anger. However, it is impossible to undo anger's effect on
virtue; at best the damage can be moderated.
Although the effect of anger--or, at least, intense
anger--is to "cut the roots (or, destroy the seeds) of virtue," this
does not actually mean that virtue is destroyed, for nothing other
than a wisdom consciousness can destroy karma. Rather, the roots or
seeds of virtue are incapacitated. Consequently, one may be reborn
many times in the miserable realms below the level of humans, or, if
born a human, will be unable to make much spiritual progress.
Tsongkhapa's attempt to explain and moderate the position
of the Indian texts is not wholly convincing. On the one hand, since
anger only temporarily incapacitates the roots or seeds of virtue, it
is not clear how it differs from other kle"sas such as pride.
Tsongkhapa himself says "cut" must mean more than "delay" but in the
final analysis it appears to mean that and nothing more. On the other
hand, even if anger means only incapacitation, its extraordinary
damage spreading over many aeons, based on as little as a moment's
outburst, seems to make liberation a practical impossibility for most
persons. Tsongkhapa's interpretation would have to be even bolder--or,
anger of the root-cutting variety would have to be clearly restricted
to only the most extraordinary moments of rage--to avoid this
untenable conclusion.
REFERENCES
Buswell, Robert
-1992 "The Path to Perdition: The Wholesome Roots and
their Eradication," in Robert Buswell and Robert Gimello (eds.) Paths
to Liberation (Honolulu: University of Hawai'i Press).
Candrakīrti nḍ.
Madhyāmakāvatāra. P 5261, P 5262, vol. 98. Edited Tibetan: Louis de La
Vallee Poussin, Madhyamakāvatāra par Candrakīrti. Bibliotheca Buddhica
IX (Osnabr™ck: Biblio Verlag, 1970). English translations: C. W.
Huntington, Jr., The Emptiness of Emptiness (University of Hawai'i
Press, 1989). Chapters 1-5: Jeffrey Hopkins, Compassion in Tibetan
Buddhism (Valois, NY: Gabriel/Snow Lion, 1980). Chapter 6: Stephen
Batchelor, in Geshe Rabten, Echoes of Voidness (London: Wisdom, 1983):
47-92.
Cozort, Daniel
-1989 "Unique Tenets of the Middle Way Consequence School:
The Systematization of the Philosophy of the Indian Buddhist
Prāsa"ngika-Mādhyamika School by the Tibetan Ge-luk-ba Scholastic
Tradition." PhḌ.
Dissertation, University of Virginia.
Dhargyey, Geshey Ngawang
-1980 Tibetan Tradition of Mental Development, 3rd edition
(Dharamsala: Library of Tibetan Works and Archives).
Gyatso, Geshe Kelsang
-1980 Meaningful to Behold (London: Wisdom).
Gyatso, Tenzin, Dalai Lama XIV nḍ.
Dalai Lama at Harvard (Ithaca: Snow Lion).
Hirakawa, Akira
-1990 A History of Indian Buddhism (Honolulu: University
of Hawai'i Press).
Hayes, Richard P.
-1994 "The Analysis of Karma in Vasubandhu's
Abhidharmako"sa-bhāṣya,"
in Katherine Young (ed.), Hermeneutical Paths to the Sacred Worlds of
India (Atlanta: Scholar's Press).
Hopkins, P. Jeffrey
-1980 Compassion in Tibetan Buddhism (Ithaca: Snow Lion).
-1983 Meditation on Emptiness (London: Wisdom).
Jamyang Shayba
-1973 ('Jams dbyang bzhad pa). Dbu ma chen mo.Great
Exposition of the Middle Way/Analysis of (Candrakīrti's) "Entrance to
(Nāgārjuna's ) 'Treatise on the Middle Way'", Treasury of Scripture
and Reasoning, Thoroughly Illuminating the Profound Meaning [of
Emptiness], Entrance for the Fortunate (dbu ma chen no/ dbu ma 'jug
pa'i mtha' dpyod lung rigs gter mdzod zab don kun gsal skal bzang 'jug
ngogs). In Collected Works of 'Jam-dbya"ns-bzad-pa'i-rdo-rje, Vol. 9,
Drashikyil edition (New Delhi: Ngawang Gelek Demo). English
translation (section on two truths): Guy Newland, The Two Truths, PhḌ.
Dissertation, University of Virginia, 1988 (not included in 1992 book
published by Snow Lion.)
Great Exposition of Tenets/Explanation of "Tenets", Sun of
the Land of Samantabhadra Brilliantly Illuminating All of Our Own and
Others' Tenets and the Meaning of the Profound [Emptiness], Ocean of
Scripture and Reasoning Fulfilling All Hopes of All Beings (grub mtha'
chen mo/grub mtha'i rnam bshad rang gzhan grub mtha' kin dang zab don
mchog tu gsal ba kun bzang zhing gi nyi ma lung rigs rgya mtsho skye
dgu'i re ba kun skong). Drashikyil edition (Mundgod: Gomang). English
translation (beginning of the Prāsa"ngika chapter): Jeffrey Hopkins in
Meditation on Emptiness (London: Wisdom, 1983).
Klein, Anne
-1994 Path to the Middle: The Spoken Scholarship of Kensur
Yeshey Tupten (Albany: State University of New York Press).
Lopez, Donald
-1992 "Paths Terminable and Interminable," in Buswell and
Gimello (eds), Paths to Liberation.
Pabongka Rinpoche
-1991 Liberation in the Palm of Your Hand (London:
Wisdom).
Pradhan, Pralhad (ed.)
-1950 Abhidharma-Samuccaya of Asa"nga (Santiniketan:
Visva-Bharati).
Rahula, Walpola (tr.)
-1971 Le Compendium de la super-doctrine (philosophie): (Abhidharmasamuccaya)
d'Asa"nga (Paris: Publications de l''Ecole Francaise d'Extreme
Orient).
"Sāntideva
-1979 Bodhisattvacaryāvatāra. (byang chub sems dpa'i spyod
pa la 'jug pa). P5272, Vol. 99. English translation: Stephen
Batchelor, A Guide to the Bodhisattva's Way of Life (Dharamsala: LTWA).
Tsongkhapa (tsong kha pa blo bzang grags pa1357-1419)
-1985 Great Exposition of the Stages of the Path/Stages of
the Path to Enlightenment Thoroughly Teaching All the Stages of
Practice of the Three Types of Beings (lam rim chen mo/skyes bu gsum
gyi rnyams su blang ba'i rim pa thams cad tshang bar ston pa'i byang
chub lam gyi rim pa). P 6001, vol. 152. The edition used for this
article is the Lhasa bya khyung edition published by Mtsho sngon mi
rigs Printing Press. Other editions have been published in Dharamsala
(Shes rig par khang, 1964) and Delhi (Ngawang Gelek, 1975).
Illumination of the Thought, Extensive Explanation of (Candrakīrti's)
"Entrance to (Nāgārjuna's) 'Treatise on the Middle Way'" (dbu ma la
'jug pa'i rgya cher bshad pa dgongs pa rab gsal). P 6143, Vol. 154.
The edition used for this article is the Dharamsala Shes rig par khang
edition. Another edition was published in Sarnath, India (Pleasure of
Elegant Sayings Press, 1973).
Wayman, Alex
-1991 Ethics of Tibet (Albany: State University of New
York Press).
NOTES
(1) Anger is not unique as a negative emotion that can
"cut the roots" of virtue. In Illumination of the Thought Tsongkhapa
cites sūtra passages collected in "Sāntideva's "Sikṣāsamuccaya
that identify other extremely counterproductive notions such as
disbelief in cause and effect, boasting about spiritual attainments
one does not have, etc. as root-cutters. He also mentions that the
Aakā"sagarbha Sūtra identifies root infractions of bodhisattva vows as
root-cutters. See Illumination: 57a.5-57b.1. Of course, none of these
are said to have the force of anger.
(2) Tibetan Tripiṭaka
764, Vol. 27 (Tokyo-Kyoto: Tibetan Tripiṭaka
Research Foundation, 1956). Cited in Tsongkhapa, Great Exposition.
(3) To represent Tibetan names, I use a modified form of
Jeffrey Hopkins' "essay phonetics" (Hopkins 1983: 19-22) system for
Lhasa dialect. I drop the hyphens and tonal marks, and I make an
exception for the name Tsongkhapa, which has become widely known in
that form (it would otherwise be spelled Dzongkaba). I use the
phonetic form because it is well known that we can't remember what we
can't pronounce, and I think that the names of the best Tibetan
scholars are worth remembering. Tibetan book titles are translated
into English to avoid the consonant-cluster nightmare of
transliterated Tibetan that alienates those who are not Tibetanists
and to avoid the phonetic form that alienates Tibetanists. The
translation of titles also reminds readers of book contents.
(4) Great Exposition of the Stages of the Path (lam rim
chen mo) is the common name for Stages of the Path to Enlightenment
Thoroughly Teaching All the Stages of Practice of the Three Types of
Beings (skyes bu gsum gyi rnyams su blang ba'i rim pa thams cad tshang
bar ston pa'i byang chub lam gyi rim pa). It is Tsongkhapa's grand
synthesis of Indian materials pertaining to the enlightenment path. It
has been partially translated by Alex Wayman (Calming the Mind and
Discerning the Real in 1978 and Ethics of Tibet in 1991). A new
translation of the entire text is in preparation by a team working
under the auspices of the Tibetan Buddhist Learning Center in
Washington, New Jersey and is scheduled for publication in three
volumes by Harper in 1996-98. My own interest in the topic of anger
was raised by my translation of the "ethical discipline" and
"patience" chapters for the project. Illumination of the Thought (dbu
ma dgongs pa rab gsal) is the common name for Illumination of the
Thought, Extensive Explanation of (Candrakīrti's) "Entrance to (Nāgārjuna's)
'Treatise on the Middle Way'" (dbu ma la 'jug pa'i rgya cher bshad pa
dgongs pa rab gsal). It is Tsongkhapa's attempt, late in life, to
clarify the thought of Candrakīrti, who he saw in turn as the most
important of Nāgārjuna's Mādhyamika successors. Since Candrakīrti's
discussion in the Madhyamakāvatāra revolves around the ten bodhisattva
grounds, Illumination is also concerned with many of the same issues
as Great Exposition and is also characterized by copious citations
from Indian texts. It has been partially translated by Hopkins (1980;
chapters 1-5) and Klein and Hopkins (Klein 1994; first part of chapter
6). Tsongkhapa makes similar statements in both sources (in fact, much
of the text of Illumination on this topic has simply been lifted from
Great Exposition. The principal difference is that in the later
Illumination he clarifies a few matters (for instance, the precise
parties to whom he believes the Indian texts refer).
(5) Identified by "Sāntideva as a "text of the Aarya-
Sarvāstivādins." The relevant portion is cited later.
(6) Although Tsongkhapa mentions Candrakīrti's and "Sāntideva's
estimates in both Illumination and Great Exposition, he reconciles the
differences in only the later work, Illumination. Candrakīrti is
particularly important for Tsongkhapa's understanding of Mādhyamika,
but "Sāntideva is particularly important for his understanding of the
topic of patience.
(7) Admitting that Prajñākaramati's commentary on the
Bodhisattvacaryāvatāra says otherwise, mentioning only "sentient
beings," Tsongkhapa says that he finds this "difficult to believe."
(8) One famous counter-example is that of Milarepa, but
his pattern of mass-murderer-turned-saint is highly unusual. Of
course, there are also instances in which a bodhisattva guru might
provoke a student's anger in order to teach the student, and I am not
certain how the tradition might work out the consequences.
(9) The extensive Gelukba sa lam (=bhūmi and mārga,
grounds and paths) literature is based on Maitreya's Abhisamayālaṃkāra
(which in turn is based on the Prajñāpāramitā literature, where the
five-path scheme can be dimly discerned) and Haribhadra's commentary;
it also uses the five-path scheme of Kamala"sīla's Bhāvanākrama
(following a much older tradition evident even in Sarvāstivādin
texts--Hirakawa 208ff.). In brief, the bodhisattva path of
accumulation begins with the initial generation of bodhicitta, and the
path of preparation with a union of calm abiding (zhi gnas, "samatha)
and special insight (lhag mthong, vipa"syanā) with emptiness (stong pa
nyid, "sūnyatā) as the object.
(10) Tenzin Gyatso: 83.
(11) The angry bodhisattva must still be a relatively low
one since a bodhisattva who has progressed past the third of the ten
bodhisattva bhumis (a pre-Mahāyāna system adapted to Mahāyāna in, for
instance, the Da"sabhūmika Sūtra) is no longer ever subject to anger.
This qualification can be found in Maitreya's Abhisamāyalaṃkāra
and elaborated in subsequent treatments of the bodhisattva path (cf.
Candrakīrti's Madhyamakāvatāra 3.13). The Gelukba scheme would place
such a person even lower. The second of the four parts of the path of
preparation is called "peak" (rtse mo, mūrdhan) because it is the end
of the period in which one can generate anger that will sever the
roots of virtue. Also, Tsongkhapa makes a distinction between
bodhisattvas whose faculties are sharp and those whose are not. The
former are the sort who needed to convince themselves that the
Buddha's teaching on emptiness was true, and therefore that Buddhahood
was attainable, before they could make the extraordinary commitment to
strive for countless aeons to free all sentient beings. Such persons
might have attained a level of understanding equivalent to the path of
preparation even before they generated bodhicitta, the effect of which
would be to undermine (though not, of course, destroy) their
predispositions to anger and desire. A later commentator, the
fifteenth century Jaydz™n Cho/oogyi Gyeltsen (rje btsun chos kyi
rgyal mtshan) who wrote the Mādhyamaka textbook--based on
Illumination--still in use by Sera Jay (se ra rje) Gelukba monastery,
went even further. He claimed that not only do intelligent persons
realize emptiness prior to generating bodhicitta, but most dull ones
do also (see Newland: 43).
(12) Translation is Hopkins (1980: 212).
(13) Illumination: 54a.5-6. Translation follows Hopkins
(1980: 210).
(14) See Hopkins (1980: 154).
(15) It may not be the case that all instances of anger
cut the roots of virtue. As we will see, instances of anger may be
differentiated on the basis of their recipients, but are there other
factors that make one instance worse than another? Tenzin Gyatso,
Dalai Lama XIV, says that it is still possible for someone past the
path of seeing to experience anger; however, since root-cutting anger
is no longer experienced past the second part of the even earlier path
of preparation, it is clear that this anger would not impel lifetimes
of suffering. The implication is that a higher bodhisattva's anger is
not as serious, perhaps because to some extent its root cause,
ignorance, has been undermined. Does this also mean that not all
instances of anger would result in severance of the roots of virtue?
Would Tsongkhapa agree with the Dalai Lama's conclusion?
(16) Buswell: 107-134.
(17) Buswell: 118-123.
(18) The seventeenth century Gelukba abbot Jamyang Shayba
('jams dbyang bzhad pa) makes this identification in his dbu ma chen
mo (Great Exposition of the Middle Way: 160a.5), which is a commentary
on Candrakīrti's Madhyamakāvatāra.
(19) Pradhan: 35/Rahula: 78:58. Cited in Buswell: 119-20.
According to Tsongkhapa's Gelukba order, the mind's emptiness of
inherent existence is a "natural lineage" (rang bzhin gnas rigs) that
is the Buddha nature of each sentient being, and hence there is no one
who will fail, eventually, to attain Buddhahood. (For a review of
reasons why some of Tsongkhapa's followers found difficulties with
these doctrines, see Lopez.) They interpret Asa"nga to mean that he
sees five lineages (rigs, gotra) for sentient beings, respectively
those who follow the path of the "Srāvakas, Pratyekabuddhas, and
Bodhisattvas, those who switch from one of the former to the latter,
and those without a lineage for liberation.
(20) According to Tsongkhapa, the four opponent powers
involve remorse for transgressions; cultivating their antidotes;
restraint; and taking refuge in cultivation of the spirit of
enlightenment (bodhicitta). Tsongkhapa does not specify, at least
here, whether these powers are sufficient to counteract all nonvirtues,
but that seems to be a commonly held opinion (cf. Pabongka Rinpoche:
218).
(21) Presumably, painful experiences must be due to
actions of previous lives or for which the person had no remorse,
etc., possibly because they had been forgotten.
(22) To be more precise, according to Gelukba exegetes,
the path of preparation is the level at which one has experienced a
union of calm abiding (zhi gnas, "samatha) and special insight (lhag
mthong, vipa"syanā)with emptiness as one's object. The realization is
powerful but is as yet one that is inferential rather than direct.
(23) This paragraph is not Tsongkhapa's example, but my
own, which I include because it seems parallel to the example he
furnishes. As I point out below, Tsongkhapa wants to distinguish
between the temporary suppression of fruitions by the ripening of
other, contrary, karmas, and the incapacitation of fruitions by anger.
That is, anger is qualitatively different from most other nonvirtues.
That is why I think that he himself would not use this as an example.
However, there seems to be no difference between the practical effects
of these nonvirtues.
(24) In Illumination: 56b.1.
(25) Great Exposition: 401.12-14.
(26) Tsongkhapa and his followers consistently interpret
the "not other than" statements in Indian Mādhyamaka as meaning "not
inherently other" since, of course, things such as seeds and sprouts
are different from each other. On the other hand, they are
individually not inherently existent (rang bzhin gyis grub pa,
svabhāvasiddhi) and do not have a relationship of inherent
otherness--a relationship that is not merely imputed by thought.
(27) Illumination: 127b.3-6.
(28) Prāpti and other means to account for the
continuation of karma, such as the ālayavijñāna of Yogacārā texts, are
rejected by Tsongkhapa as entities not included in the conventions of
the world (which he thinks are, in contrast, upheld by sūtras of
definitive meaning and in the ultimate commentarial tradition of
Prāsa"ngika-Mādhyamika), not to mention the fact that as described by
their proponents they could be established only by ultimate analysis.
This is a major topic of the "unique tenets of Prāsa"ngika" section of
Jamyang Shayba's Great Exposition of Tenets (grub mtha' chen mo),
which I translated as part of my dissertation. For a recent discussion
of Vaibhāṣika
positions and how they are critiqued by Vasubandhu's
Abhidharmako"sa-bhāṣya,
see Hayes.
(29) Of course, it also raises the question of how wisdom
could destroy seeds. This is reminiscent of a discussion by Jamyang
Shayba (Great Exposition of the Middle Way: 628.3-.5) on the "disintegratedness"
of the obstructions to omniscience (shes sgrib, jñeyāvaraṇa)
for Buddhas. To become Buddhas, of course, necessitated the
destruction of those obstructions, but Jamyang Shayba, wishing to
avoid saying that Buddhas have anything like a taint in their
continūms, maintains that the disintegratedness of obstructions to
omniscience does not exist. His reasoning: in order to be a
functioning entity, something must be capable of producing an effect,
and this disintegratedness cannot. Instead, the obstructions to
omniscience are completely "extinguished into the dharmadhātu." I have
discussed arguments for and against Jamyang Shayba's position in my
dissertation.
(30) Although I doubt that they are that to which
Tsongkhapa refers, there are seeds that are capable of producing more
than one effect; e.g., a single act of killing is said to be capable
of ripening into numerous lifetimes in the miserable realms. Even if
some effects had ripened, those seeds would continue to exist.
(31) A single action produces a "seed" (sa bon, bīja) for
a future effect, a "predisposition" (bags chags, vāsanā) or tendency
to repeat that type of action, and an environmental effect of
contributing to the causal conditions for the world shared with other
beings. Cf. Dhargyey: 87-88.
(32) Illumination: 57a.2-.3. I follow Hopkins'
translation.
(33) As Donald Lopez has shown (1992), Tsongkhapa seems
not to have believed that all sentient beings would inevitably reach
Buddhahood, bringing an end to saṃsāra;
on the other hand, he would certainly claim that it is possible for
all of them to attain liberation and omniscience.
(34) Great Exposition: 401.19-20.
(35) Great Exposition: 401.17-19.
(36) This is a summary of Great Exposition: 405-414.
(37) This comes close to implying that every unpleasant
occurrence is a direct result of one's own karma. Tsongkhapa would not
say this, I think; however, he might argue that every unpleasant
experience at least indirectly stems from one's past actions insofar
as one's actions are a part of the collective karma that creates and
sustains a shared environment.
(38) Cf. Buswell for an analysis of the importance of
giving, in particular, for the spiritual path. Giving can be seen not
only as a virtuous act but one that is a conditioner of insight.
(39) Kensur Yeshey Tupten, a great twentieth century
Gelukba scholar, adds (Klein: 85) that even prior to the direct
cognition of emptiness that begins to destroy karma on the path of
seeing and above, conceptual understanding of emptiness also purifies
the seeds established by anger.
(40) Great Exposition: 402.4-6.
(41) Illumination: 55a.5-6. My translation follows Hopkins
(1980: 212).
Copyright 1995
--o0o--
|