Critical Questions Towards
A Naturalized Concept Of Karma In Buddhism
By Dale S. Wright
Department of Religious Studies, Occidental College, Los Angeles,
California
ISSN 1076-9005; Volume 11, 2004
---o0o---
Abstract
Abstract: In an effort to articulate a naturalized concept
of karma for the purposes of contemporary ethical reflection, this
paper raises four critical questions about the Buddhist doctrine of
karma. The paper asks:
1- About the advisability of linking the concept of karma
to assurance of ultimate cosmic justice through the doctrine of
rebirth;
2- About the effects of this link on the quest for human
justice in the social, economic, and political spheres of culture;
3- About the kinds of rewards that the doctrine of karma
attaches to virtuous action, whether they tend to be necessary or
contingent consequences; and
4- About the extent to which karma is best conceived
individually or collectively. The paper ends with suggestions for how
a non-metaphysical concept of karma might function and what role it
might play in contemporary ethics.
The Buddha warned (1) that karma is so mysterious a
process that it is essentially unfathomable, declaring it one of the
four topics not suited to healthy philosophical meditation because it
leads to “vexation and madness. Nevertheless, it is essential that we
engage in the processes of critical thinking about the concept of
karma, thereby taking the same risks that many Asian Buddhists have
also taken. It is important for us to do so because Buddhist (and
Hindu) teachings on karma and moral life have now entered contemporary
currents of Western thought and culture, and deserve to be scrutinized
for their potential value and weaknesses. The risk is serious, of
course, because in Asia karma is the primary concept governing the
moral sphere of culture. Westerners have faced doubts about critical
thinking in this same sphere of culture, when early modern thinkers
wondered whether moral conduct would survive critical reflection on
the concepts of theistic judgment and heavenly reward. Most have
concluded that the benefits of critical thinking about morality
outweigh the risks, and that the possibility of further development
and refinement in the sphere of human morality warrants energetic
effort.
The primary reason that karma is a promising ethical
concept for us today is that it appears to propose a natural
connection between a human act and its appropriate consequence, or, in
traditional terms, between sin and suffering, virtue and reward. The
connection requires no supernatural intervention: we suffer or succeed
because of the natural outcome of our actions themselves, rather than
through the subsequent intervention of divine punishment or reward.
Moral errors contain their own penalties as natural consequences, and
every virtue encompasses its own reward. Although some dimensions of
Western culture presuppose such an arrangement today, it is
instructive to recall that this kind of understanding wasn’t
articulated in the West until Rousseau in the eighteenth century. (2)
Throughout Asia, karma defines the ethical dimension of
culture and remains the key to understanding Buddhist morality. Karma
is the teaching that tells practitioners that it matters what they do
throughout their lives, and how they do it. It articulates a close
relationship between what one chooses to do and who or what that
person becomes over time. The extraordinary sophistication of this
early concept should, in fact, be counted as one of the most
significant achievements of south Asian culture, and an impressive
gift to contemporary ethical thinking globally.
A number of scholars (3) have claimed that one of the
primary contributions of Buddhism to Indian culture was that it
“ethicized” an earlier pre-ethical concept of karma in extending it
beyond the sphere of religious ritual by applying it not just to
ritual behaviors that pleased the gods but to all good acts. (4)
The domain of “all good acts” is, of course, the sphere of
ethics as we know it today, and the applicability of the concept of
karma to this sphere is the primary issue of this essay. The essay is
based on the thesis that a naturalistic concept of karma, inherent in
the concept as articulated in the many Buddhist versions of it, can
and should be developed, and that with further cultivation for the
emerging context of contemporary global culture, the concept of karma
could constitute a major element in the ethical thinking of the
future. Doing that, however, requires critical thinking. This essay,
therefore, raises questions about four dimensions of the concept of
karma as it has been understood in the history of Buddhism. Each area
of questioning is offered as a way to begin to hone the concept, to
separate it from elements of supernatural thinking, and to work
towards locating those elements that might be most effective today in
the domain of ethics. Following these four exercises in critical
thinking, a few suggestions are offered about the emergence of a
naturalized concept of karma.
The first dimension of the Buddhist doctrine of karma that
warrants reflective scrutiny is its assertion of ultimate cosmic
justice. All of the world’s major religions have longstanding
traditions of promise that, at some point, good and evil lives will be
rewarded with good and evil consequences, and that everyone will
receive exactly what they deserve. But all of these religions are also
forced to admit that this doctrine contradicts what we sometimes
experience in our lives. Good people may just as readily be severely
injured or die from an accident, or die early of disease, as anyone
else, and people who have lived unjustly and unfairly will not
necessarily experience any deprivation in their lives. Some people
seem to receive rewards in proportion to the merit of their lives,
while others do not. Among those who don’t appear to get what they
deserve, some seem to receive more than merit would dictate, and
others, less.
That all of these outcomes are common and unsurprising to
us should lead us to question the kind of relationship that exists
between merit and reward. One way to face this realization is to
conclude, at least provisionally, that the cosmos is largely
indifferent to the sphere of human merit as well as to our
expectations of justice. If a morally sound person is no more or no
less likely to die early of a disease than anyone else, then maturity
and honesty of vision on this matter may require that we question
traditional assumptions that cosmic justice must prevail. Although we
certainly care about matters of justice, it may be that beyond the
human sphere we will not be able to find evidence of that kind of
concern.
The religious claim that there is a supernatural
connection between moral merit and ultimate destiny may derive from
our intuitive sense that there ought to be such a connection. We all
sense that there ought to be justice, even in settings where it seems
to be lacking. That the corporate criminal ought to be punished, that
the innocent child ought to live well rather than to suffer from a
devastating disease, and that some things ought to be different from
what they appear to be, are all manifestations of our deep seated
sense of justice. Virtue and reward, vice and punishment, ought to be
systematically related, and where they are not, we all feel a sense of
impropriety. But whether that now intuitive internal sense is
sufficient reason to postulate a supernatural scheme of cosmic justice
beyond our understanding and experience is an open question that has
remained as closed in Buddhism as it has in other religions. The form
that this closure takes in Buddhism is the doctrine of rebirth, which
plays the same role that heaven does in theistic traditions as
ultimate guarantor of justice. As it is traditionally conceived in
Asia, karma requires the metaphysical doctrine of rebirth to support
its often counter-experiential claims about the ultimate triumph of
cosmic justice for the individual.
The second question about the doctrine of karma follows
from the first, and is, in fact, the primary critique that has been
leveled against the idea since it has been introduced to the West.
This is that the idea of karma may be socially and politically
disempowering in its cultural effect, that without intending to do
this, karma may in fact support social passivity or acquiescence in
the face of oppression of various kinds. This possible negative effect
derives again from the link formed between karma and rebirth in order
to posit large-scale cosmic justice over long and invisible stretches
of time where other more immediate forms of justice appear not to
exist. If one assumes that cosmic justice prevails over numerous
lifetimes, and that therefore the situations of inequality that people
find themselves in are essentially of their own making through moral
effort or lack of it in previous lives, then it may not seem either
necessary or even fair to attempt to equalize opportunities among
people or to help those in desperate circumstances. For example, if
you believe that a child being severely abused by his family is now
receiving just reward for his past sins, you may find insufficient
reason to intervene even when that abuse appears to be destructive to
the individual child and to the society.
Now, of course, it is an open question, an historical and
social-psychological question, whether or to what extent the doctrines
of karma and rebirth have ever really had this effect. We know very
well that Buddhist concepts of compassion have prominent places in the
various traditions, and we can all point to Buddhist examples of
compassionate social effort on behalf of the poor and the needy.
Nevertheless, we can see where the logic of this belief easily leads,
in the minds of some people at least, and we can suspect that it may
have unjustifiably diminished or undermined concern for the poor and
the suffering in all Buddhist cultures. The link between karma and
rebirth can reasonably be taken to justify nonaction in the
socio-economic and political spheres, and may help provide rational
support for acquiescence to oppressive neighbors, laws, and regimes.
If and when this does occur, then the Buddhist teaching of nonviolence
can be distorted into a teaching of nonaction and passivity, and be
subject to criticism as a failure of courage and justice.
If the truth is that the cosmos is simply indifferent to
human questions of merit and justice, that truth makes it all the more
important that human beings attend to these matters themselves. If
justice is a human concept, invented and evolving in human minds and
culture, and no where else, then it is up to us alone to see that we
follow through on it. If justice is not structured into the universe
itself, then it will have been a substantial mistake to leave it up to
the universe to see that justice is done. Although, given our
finitude, human justice will always be imperfect, it may be all the
justice we have. Moreover, the fact that religious traditions,
including Buddhism, have claimed otherwise may be insufficient reason
to accept the assertion of a cosmic justice beyond the human as the
basis for our actions in the world.
A third area of inquiry in which to engage the concept of
karma concerns the nature of the reward or consequence that might be
expected to follow from morally relevant actions. In pursuing this
line of questioning, I will be employing a distinction borrowed from
Alasdair MacIntyre that is now common to contemporary ethics between
goods that are externally or contingently related to a given practice,
and goods that are internal to a practice and that cannot be acquired
in any other way. (5) Because the practice under consideration here is
any morally relevant action, we want to distinguish between goods or
rewards that may accompany that moral act, but which are only
contingently and externally related to it, and rewards that are
directly linked to the practice, available through no other means, and
therefore internal to that specific practice.
If we look at a single act, say an act of extraordinary
generosity or kindness, such as when someone goes far out of her way
to help someone else through a problem that he has brought upon
himself, we can see many possibilities for rewards that might accrue
through some contingency entailed in that relation. The person helped
may in fact be wealthy, and offer a large sum of money in grateful
reciprocity. Members of his family may honor the practitioner of
kindness, and her reputation in the community for compassion and
character might grow. She may become known as a citizen of
extraordinary integrity, which could lead to all kinds of indirect
rewards. These are all good consequences, and all deserved, but also
all contingent outcomes, all goods that are external to the moral act
itself. They may or may not be forthcoming. Indeed, on occasion
contingent misunderstanding may give rise to exactly the opposite
outcome -- the same act of generosity may be misunderstood, resented,
reviled, or lead to a denigrated reputation that the person never
overcomes.
The rewards or goods internal to that act of kindness are
directly related to the act, and aren’t contingent on anything but the
act. When we act generously, we do something incremental to our
character -- we shape ourselves slightly further into a person who
understands how to act generously, is inclined to do so, and does so
with increasing ease. We etch that way of behaving just a little more
firmly into our character, into who we are. That is true whether the
act is positive or negative in character. (6) Generosity, when it
becomes an acquired feature of our character, becomes a virtue, in
fact one of the central Buddhist virtues, the first of the six
perfections, for example. “A virtue is an acquired human quality the
possession and exercise of which tends to enable us to achieve those
goods which are internal to practices and the lack of which
effectively prevents us from achieving any such goods.” (7) This is to
say that acts of generosity may or may not give rise to external goods
like rewards of money or prestige, but they do give rise to a
transformation in character that makes us generous, kind, and
concerned about the well-being of others. Internal goods derive
naturally from the practice as cause.
Our question, then, is what kinds of rewards, or goods,
does the doctrine of karma correlate to virtuous or nonvirtuous acts,
and how should we assess that dimension of the doctrine? Familiarity
with the tradition prevents us from giving a univocal answer to this
question: different texts and different teachers promise many
different kinds of rewards for karmically significant acts, depending
on who they are and who they happen to be addressing. Both internal
and external goods are commonly brought into play. From acts of
generosity we get everything from the virtue of generosity as an
internal good to great wealth, an external good, with a variety of
specific alternatives in between. Teachers often lean heavily one way
or the other, from emphasis on external goods such as health and
wealth to a strict focus on the internal goods of character, the
development of virtues like wisdom and compassion. Consider this
example from the Dalai Lama, where he is primarily interested in
external goods. “As a result of stealing,” he writes, “one will lack
material wealth.” (8) Because we all know that successful thieves and
corporate criminals may or may not live their lives lacking in
material wealth, we can only agree with this claim insofar as we
assume that the author is here referring to an afterlife, some life
beyond the end of this one. That is to say that only the metaphysics
of rebirth can make this statement plausible. Otherwise, the doctrine
of karma cannot truthfully guarantee such an outcome of external
rewards.
Had he been focused on internal goods, he might have said
that, as a result of stealing, one will have deeply troubled relations
to other people, as well as a distorted relation to material goods. As
a result of stealing one will find compassion and intimacy more
difficult, be further estranged from the society in which one lives,
and feel isolated and unable to trust others. As a result of stealing,
one will become even more likely to commit other unhealthy acts, and
may ultimately find oneself in an unfulfilled and diminished
existence. These results of the act of stealing have a direct relation
to the act; every act pushes one further in some direction of
character formation or another, and further instantiates us in some
particular relationship to the world. External goods, while certainly
important, cannot be so easily guaranteed, except insofar as one
offers that guarantee metaphysically by referring to lives beyond the
current one.
Although, promises of personal rebirth aside, there would
appear to be no necessary connection between moral achievement and
external rewards, there is a sense in which moral achievement does
often make external rewards more likely, even if this is never a
relation of necessity. This is true because the more human beings
enter the equation, the more likely it is that a human sense of
justice will intervene, drawing some connection between virtue and
reward, or sin and suffering. People who characteristically treat
others with kindness and just consideration are often treated kindly
themselves, although not always. Those who are frequently mean
spirited and selfish are often treated with distain. Honesty in
business often pays off in the form of trusting, faithful customers,
while the habit of cheating customers will often come back to haunt
the merchant. These dimensions of karma and of ethical relations are
clear to us, and we are thankful that they exist. But it would seem
that their existence is human and social, rather than structured into
the cosmos.
Therefore, all we can say is that things often work this
way, not that they always do, or that they must. Sometimes
unscrupulous businessmen thrive; on occasion, kindness and honesty go
completely unrewarded. These occurrences make it impossible for us to
claim a necessary relation between moral merit and external forms of
reward. Although it is clearly true that to some extent virtue is its
own reward, what we cannot claim is that other kinds of reward are
meted out in the same way. Evidence shows us that they are not, even
if the human exercise of justice often directs external rewards
towards those who are deserving.
Let me summarize the forgoing by saying: how you comport
yourself ethically has at least three ramifications:
1- It shapes your character and helps determine who or
what you become;
2- It helps shape others and the society in which you
live, now and into the future; and
3-
It encourages others to treat you in ways that correspond to your
character.
They will often do onto you as you have done onto them,
although not always. The first and second outcomes can be counted as
goods internal to ethical action; our actions do shape us and they do
have an effect on the world. The third is external, that is,
contingent, in that it may or may not follow from the ethical act. The
more human justice there is, the more the distribution of external
goods is likely to match the extent of our merit.
Thus, insofar as we can gather evidence on this matter,
some dissociation between merit and external goods is important to
maintain. Although good acts do lead to the development of good
character, being good does not always or necessarily lead to a life of
good fortune. Therefore, if there is a contingent relation between
external goods as rewards and merit, it would be wise to articulate a
system of ethics and a doctrine of karma that do not rely heavily on
this relation in spite of the longstanding Buddhist tradition of doing
so for purposes of moral motivation.
The fourth and final dimension of the concept of karma
that I want to examine is the extent to which karma can be adequately
conceived as a consequence or destiny that is individual, as opposed
to one that is social or collective. Although there are a few
interesting places in Buddhist philosophy where a collective dimension
to karma is broached, in Asanga and Vasubandhu for example, I think
that it is true to say that this concept has been overwhelmingly
understood in individual terms, that is, that the karma produced by my
acts is mine primarily, rather than ours collectively. (9) For the
most part, references to karma in contemporary Buddhist literature
follow the same individualized pattern. From my point of view, there
are serious philosophical difficulties with this way of understanding
the impact of our lives, however. Perhaps most strikingly, the view
that my acts and their repercussions remain enclosed in a personal
continuum that never dissipates into the larger society and continues
to be forever “mine” reinforces a picture of the world as composed of
a large number of discreet and isolated souls, a view that a great
deal of Buddhist thought has sought to undermine. The articulation of
this view among the Jains, in Samkhya, and others, however, clearly
shows the powerful impact of the concern for ultimate individual
destiny in the Indian intellectual/religious world around the time
that Buddhism was developing its vision.
Although the primary direction of Buddhist thinking may
have been to undercut the entire question of ultimate individual
destiny through the alternative possibility of no self, the question
has continued to surface and to demand an answer. It may very well be,
however, that Buddhist attempts to satisfy the desire behind the
question by offering the concept of rebirth to allay fears about the
continuation of individual existence has the additional and unwanted
effect of blocking further development along the alternative paths
clearly laid out in the early teachings. It stands in the way of the
achievement of a broader vision of the meanings of no self, and a more
effective and mature understanding of the ways each of us continue to
affect the future beyond our personal lives. Personal anxieties about
death are a powerful force in the mind, so strong that they can
prevent other impersonal and trans-individual conceptions from rising
to the cultural surface.
The line of thinking that began to develop most explicitly
in early Mahayana texts, which imagined complex interrelations among
individuals, recognized that the consequences of any act in the world
could not be easily localized and isolated, and that effects radiate
out from causes in an ultimately uncontainable fashion, rendering
lines of partition between selves and between all entities in the
world significantly more porous and malleable than we tend to assume.
Expanding the image of the Bodhisattva, Buddhists began to see how
lines of influence and outcome co-mingle, along family lines and among
friends, co-workers, and co-citizens, such that the future for others
arises dependent in part upon my acts, and I arise dependent in part
upon the shaping powers of the accumulating culture around me. This
type of thinking, based heavily on the expanding meaning of dependent
origination, was forcefully present in several dimensions of Buddhist
ethics. My suspicion, however, is that we have yet to see the
development of this aspect of Buddhism to the extent of its potential,
and that it has been continually redirected by what must have seemed
more pressing questions about individual destiny.
As an example of a possible pattern of redirection,
consider the development of merit transfer, the idea that one might
give the rewards from one of your own good acts to another person
whose karmic status might be in greater jeopardy. Mahayana Buddhists
were, of course, particularly attracted to this idea; they sought ways
to develop an unselfish concern for the spiritual welfare of all
sentient beings, and focused intently on methods enabling them to get
out from under the self-centered implications of a personal spiritual
quest. The idea that they could pursue the good in their own quest,
and then in a compassionate and unselfish meditative gesture,
contemplate giving to others whatever good had resulted from that act,
seemed an excellent middle path between selfish personal quests and
compassion for others. But one effect of this teaching was that it
tended to picture the karma or the goodness of an act as a
self-enclosed package that was theirs alone, and that could be
generously given away at some later point if circumstances warranted.
As a meditative device used to prevent individuals from coveting and
hoarding their own spiritual merit, this may on occasion have been
effective. But a problem looms when a skillful meditative device is
taken out of that contemplative setting of mental self-cultivation and
treated as a picture of what really does happen when we do good
things.
It is important to remember that many Buddhist moral
teachings are not first of all prescriptions about how to treat
others, but rather prescriptions for how to treat your own mind in
meditation so that you become the kind of moral person that the
tradition envisioned. While it may be very good for you, having done a
good deed, to humble yourself in meditation on it by picturing
yourself giving the merit of that act to others, it is not good for
you to misunderstand the moral enterprise by reifying the terms and
processes operative within it. What kind of magical or supernatural
entity would karma have to be to make such a gift of merit make sense?
Focusing so intently on your own moral merit, it is also inevitable
that you come to realize that donating your merit to another is itself
a really good and generous act, one that can’t help but win you lots
of good merit.
What began as a way to drop the meritorious self from
consideration, ends up slipping it in through the back door in such a
way that the entire specter of merit transfer becomes yet another way
to picture yourself as deserving of merit. When seen from the outside,
this is doubly problematic, because the one to whom you are supposedly
being generous, in fact, gets nothing because, after all, this is
mental exercise, while you picture yourself doubling your own merit,
thereby cultivating exactly the pride and self-satisfaction that you
wanted to overcome. If the end pursued is understood in terms of
humility and unselfishness, entangling yourself in a mental economy of
merit calculation and exchange is not likely to be effective. The
practices of merit transfer just fit too smoothly into old habits of
self-concern, and all too readily block the development of kinds of
selflessness envisioned in the bodhisattva ideal. The literal and
highly reified conception of karma often presupposed in the practices
of merit transfer are philosophically problematic, as well as
counterproductive to the effort to understand karma as a viable
possibility for contemporary ethics.
There are a variety of ways in which an individualized
concept of karma continues to perpetuate itself in spite of a wealth
of ideas in the Buddhist tradition that would mitigate against it. The
basic ideas of impermanence, dependent origination, no self, and later
extensions of these ideas such as emptiness are prominent among them.
But all of these ideas run aground on the concept of rebirth, and it
is there that karma is most problematic. All four critical questions
raised in this paper about karma derive their impact from the
association that karma has with rebirth.
The question of rebirth and afterlife is as complicated as
it is interesting, and therefore not one that I’ll take up in this
setting. But let me simply indicate the direction philosophical
questioning on this issue might take -- just two points. First, if
this really is an open question about what happens to people after
they die, then we would expect that evidence will need to play at
least some role, and we would assume that scientific investigation is
the best way to gather and assess it. But here we encounter an
unsurprising division between pious Hindus and Buddhists who write
books gathering what seems to them the incontrovertible evidence for
reincarnation, and Western scientists who, seeing no evidence
whatsoever, don’t even raise the question. This is to say that,
constrained by a variety of traditional and modern doctrines, this
question hasn’t been asked in a serious way, both out of deference to
religious belief and because the question itself eludes conclusive
response because what it pursues is by definition beyond the world in
which we live, that is, fully metaphysical. That leaves most of us in
the position of needing to sort out the possibilities ourselves, but
in the meantime the most honest and therefore spiritually and
intellectually compelling response is to admit that we simply don’t
know what happens to us after we die. Better, it would seem, to allow
the mystery and gravity of human mortality to press upon us, and to
stimulate our asking the kinds of questions that reflect our deepest
human concerns, rather than to leap in one direction or the other on
the question of afterlife.
The second point, however, is the difficulty that
Buddhists have had historically in getting a doctrine of rebirth to
cohere with their other central values. Those of us who have read
through Abhidharma literature are familiar with the contortions that
Buddhist intellectuals went through in the process of explaining what
rebirth might mean in view of the Buddhist claim that there is no
permanent or substantial self because all things are both impermanent
and dependent on other impermanent conditions. Wherever in Buddhist
thought rebirth is given a strong and substantial role, no self and
other dimensions of the teachings are reduced in significance.
Wherever the teaching of no self and related doctrinal elements are
given strong and consistent application, very little is left that
rebirth could mean. Philosophers in the future will continue to raise
questions about the tension between these two early and important
dimensions in Buddhist thought, and to examine what possibilities for
thought were left unexplored in the Buddhist tradition due to logical
difficulties on this one issue. For some, it has already been tempting
to suspect that the idea of rebirth in Buddhism is an intellectual
relapse, a place within the teachings where practitioners were simply
unable or unwilling to consider the radical consequences of their
teachings, and where they may have fallen prey to the dangers of
grasping for the immortal self, or for the kinds of permanence and
security that Buddhist psychology warned against so perceptively.
These two areas, I suspect, will be the places where the debate about
rebirth and its role in the workings of karma will tend to focus. But
we’ll see; these are questions that require cautious, delicate
treatment because they are located close to the life force that
motivates human beings. But that’s exactly why they need to be raised
as real questions
In several respects, rebirth stands in the way of our
understanding karma in purely ethical terms. Rebirth encourages us:
1- To assume a concept of cosmic justice for which we have
insufficient evidence;
2- To ignore issues of justice in this life on the grounds
of speculation about future lives;
3- To focus our hopes on external rewards for our actions, like wealth
and status in a future life rather than on the construction of
character in this one; and
4- To conceive of our lives in strictly individual terms.
As a personal continuum through many lives, rather than
collectively, where individuals share in a communal destiny,
contributing their lives and efforts to that collective destiny.
Although at the time when Buddhism first emerged, karma and rebirth
continued to be linked together in order to make the newly emerging
domain of ethics viable, today, ironically, given the cultural
evolution of ethical understanding, karma may need to be disconnected
from the metaphysics of rebirth in order to continue the development
of Buddhist ethics. (10) If the early Buddhists did ethicize the
concept of karma by lifting it out of the sphere of religious ritual
by applying it to all of our morally relevant actions, then carrying
through on that ethicization will require that the link between karma
and rebirth be questioned, perhaps altered. Among Buddhists today,
educated in a world of science and favorably disposed to contemporary
standards for the articulation of truth, a naturalized concept of
karma without supernatural preconditions will more likely be both
persuasive and motivationally functional. (11)
How would we develop such a concept? Here are just a few
suggestions. A naturalistic theory of karma would treat choice and
character as mutually determining -- each arising dependent on the
other. It would show how the choices you make, one by one, shape your
character, and how the character that you have constructed, choice by
choice, sets limits on the range of possibilities that you will be
able to consider in each future decision. Karma implies that once you
have made a choice and acted on it, it will always be with you, and
you will always be the one who at that moment and under those
conditions embraced that path of action. The past, on this view, is
never something that once happened to you and is now over; instead, it
is the network of causes and conditions that has already shaped you
and that is right now setting conditions for every choice and move you
make. From the very moment of an act on, you are that choice, which
has been appropriated into your character along with countless others.
In this light human freedom becomes highly visible, and awesome in its
gravity, but is noticeable only to one who has realized the
far-reaching and irreversible impact on oneself and others of choices
made, of karma.
The concept of karma brings this pattern of freedom in
self-cultivation clearly to the fore, and does so with great insight
and natural subtly. It highlights a structure of personal
accountability in which every act contains its own internal, natural
rewards or consequences, even if Buddhists sometimes succumbed to the
temptation to offer a variety of external rewards as well. Although
money does talk, promising it when it may or may not be forthcoming is
a questionable strategy of motivation. Better to teach, as Buddhists
have, that the best things in life are free, and that the very best of
these is the freedom to cultivate oneself into someone who is wise,
insightful, compassionate, and magnanimous. (12) This freedom,
however, operates under strict and always fluctuating conditions. A
mature concept of karma would encourage people to recognize the
finitude of freedom and choice, and all of the ways we are shaped by
forces far beyond our control. Although always attempting to extend
our ethical imaginations, and therefore our freedom, failure
simultaneously to recognize the encompassing forces of nature,
society, and history places us in a precarious position, and renders
our choices naive. Our choices and our lives originate dependent on
these larger forces, and in view of them, mindfulness and reverence
are appropriate responses.
If the solitary ethical decisions we have been focusing on
so far have the power to move us in the direction of greater forms of
human excellence, then how much more so the unconscious “non-choices”
that we make every day in the form of habits and customs that deepen
over time and engrave their mark into our character. Some accounts of
karma are exceptionally insightful in that their understanding of
character development takes full account of the enormous importance of
ordinary daily practice or customs of behavior, what we habitually do
during the day often without reflection or choice -- the ways we do
our work and manage our time, the ways we daydream, or cultivate
resentment, or lose ourselves in distractions, down to the very way we
eat and breathe.
This is clearly a strong point in Buddhist ethics. On this
understanding of karma, which was closely related to the development
of meditation, ethics is largely a matter of daily practice,
understood as the self-conscious cultivation of ordinary life and
mentality towards the approximation of an ideal defined by images of
human excellence, the awakened arhats and bodhisattvas. (13) To an
extent not found in other religious and philosophical traditions,
Buddhists saw that ethics is only rarely about difficult and
monumental decisions, and that, in preparing yourself for life, it is
much more important to focus on what you do with yourself moment by
moment than it is to attempt to imagine how you will solve the major
moral crises when they arrive. They seem to have realized that it is
only through disciplined practices of daily self-cultivation that you
would be in a mental position to handle the big issues when they do
come up. They also claimed, insightfully, that the self is malleable
and open to this kind of ethical transformation, and here we see the
impact of the concept of no-self as it was developed in various
dimensions of the tradition.
Moreover, the Buddhist doctrine of no-self is one of the
best among several places in the teachings where we can begin to see
beyond the individual interpretation of karma that has dominated the
tradition so far. If karma is to be a truly comprehensive teaching
about human actions and their effects, extensive development of all of
the ways in which the effects of our acts radiate into other selves
and into social structures will need to be grafted onto the doctrine
of karma as it currently stands. This extension of the doctrine has
already begun, however, and will not be difficult to pursue because it
can be grounded on the extraordinary Mahayana teaching of emptiness,
the Buddhist vision of the interpenetration of all beings. Following
this vision, we can imagine a collective understanding of karma that
overcomes limitations deriving from the concept’s original foundation
in the individualized spirituality of early Buddhist monasticism.
A naturalized philosophical account of the Buddhist idea
of karma can, it seems to me, insightfully reflect these and other
dimensions of our human situation. Separated from elements of
supernatural thinking that have been associated with karma since its
inception, its basic tenets of freedom, decision, and accountability
are impressive, and clearly show us something important about the
human situation, including the project of self-construction, both
individually and collectively conceived. I conclude, therefore,
imagining elements in the doctrine of karma having the potential to be
truly effective in the effort to design concepts of ethical education
that are both honest to the requirements of thinking in our time, and
profoundly enabling in the quest for human excellence.
Notes
(1) Aṅguttara
Nikāya: iv, 77.
(2) See Susan Neiman, Evil in Modern Thought, Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 2002.
(3) Richard Gombrich and Gananath Obeyesekere among them.
(4) Although not a historian of early Indian culture, I
suspect that the ethicization of the concept of karma was occurring
not just in Buddhist monastic circles but more widely in other
avant-garde segments of Indian culture at the same time.
(5) Alaisdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, Notre Dame:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1981, p. 188.
(6) The first thing that accrues from an act of this sort
is that someone is helped, something good has been done to the world
out beyond the practitioner. But my focus here is on the rewards that
come to the agent.
(7) Alaisdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, p. 191.
(8) Dalai Lama, The Way to Freedom: Core Teachings of
Tibetan Buddhism. San Francisco: Harper, 1994. p. 100.
(9) See William Waldron, The Buddhist Unconscious, London:
Routledge/Curzon, 2003, pp. 160-169. Return to text
(10) In a book just released as this essay came to
completion, Robert Thurman articulates exactly the opposite point on
the concept of rebirth: that without a belief in individual
immortality -- a theory of the soul -- a fully ethical life is not
possible. While respecting the motivation and sincerity of those who
do consider the idea of rebirth to be essential both to Buddhism and
to enlightened life, I disagree with the arguments provided, and find
adherence to contemporary standards of critical thinking the most
compelling consideration. See Infinite Life: Seven Virtues for Living
Well, New York: Riverhead Books, 2004.
(11) Winston L. King explores the question of the
separability of karma and rebirth, concluding that “a doctrine of
karmic rebirth is not essential to a viable and authentic Buddhist
ethic in the West,” in “A Buddhist Ethic Without Karmic Rebirth,” in
the Journal of Buddhist Ethics, Volume 1, 1994.
(12) The question of what to do about people who can only
be motivated by promises of external rewards is an important social
question, but not one within the scope of a philosophical effort to
reflect on the truth of the matter or on what the rest of us should
believe for motivational purposes.
(13) For the connection between meditation and Buddhist
ethics, see Georges Dreyfus,“Meditation as Ethical Activity,” Journal
of Buddhist Ethics, Vol. 2, 1995.
--o0o--
|