The Lotus Sutra and Health Care Ethics
By Robert E. Florida
Professor of Religion Brandon University Brandon,
Manitoba Canada
florida@brandonu.ca
---o0o---
Contents
Buddhist Medical Ethical Principles
Autonomy
Non-maleficence or Ahimsa
Justice
Compassion and Beneficence
Veracity
References to Medicine in the Lotus Sutra
Conclusion
In the last several years there has been an increase in
interest in the field of Buddhist ethics, particularly health care
ethics. In this paper I will review the medical implications found in
the Lotus Suutra. I will first discuss some general ethical principles
that apply in health care with reference to the Lotus Suutra, and then
go on to specific references in the sutra to medicine.
Buddhist medical ethical principles
In traditional Buddhist societies, medical ethics, as a
systematic formulation of principles and their application to cases,
has not been a major concern. That is not to say that Buddhists have
ever ignored illness and health care. On the contrary, the metaphor of
the Buddha as the supreme physician, who cures the ills of the world
and of the individual sufferer, is ancient and major in the Dharma
(1). Furthermore, caring for the sick both within and without the
monastic order has been understood as an excellent way to manifest
such primary virtues as compassion and friendship.
Nonetheless, it is only recently that there have been
attempts to work out systems of health care ethics in Buddhist
contexts (2). One of the latest and most ambitious is Buddhism and
Bioethics by Damien Keown (3). His general theoretical approach is
based mainly on Theravaada primary texts, and centres Buddhist ethics
on three "basic goods": life, knowledge (prajna), and friendship (4).
These three values inform the next lower level, the level of precepts
or ethical rules. Precepts in turn guide decision-making in specific
ethical situations.
Respect for life (ahimsa), the first of the "basic goods"
according to Keown, is doubtless one of the pillars of Buddhist ethics
and generally pervades the Lotus Suutra. It is a key to Buddhist
health care ethics and will be discussed below. Knowledge (prajna) as
the second "basic good" or core principle of Buddhist ethics in
Keown's analysis is also very generally acknowledged as central in
Buddhist thought. Prajna is both the supreme paramita in the
bodhisattva path and the culmination of cultivation of mind in
Theravaada traditions. It pervades the Lotus Suutra. Prajna is often
coupled with karuna (compassion) as summing up the Mahaayaana or
bodhisattva path. Together, artfully supporting one another, they lead
the practitioner to realise his or her Buddha nature. Upaaya (skilful
means), a fundamental theme which runs throughout the Lotus Suutra,
can be understood as identical to karuna.
Keown, however, takes friendship rather than karuna/upaaya
as the third "basic good" (5). Friendship as a Buddhist ideal, he
argues, is a complex bundle of rules, virtues, behaviours, and the
like which guide us in our relations with all other living creatures.
Friendship includes compassion (karuna) when appropriate, but much
more as well. Identifying friendship as a basic Buddhist good is one
of the innovations (a fruitful one in my view) in Keown's book. In the
Lotus Suutra the qualities of friendship that Keown describes are
found in the relationships between the various characters. For
example, the parable of Devadatta in chapter twelve shows the efficacy
of friendship, which goes beyond one particular lifetime into future
incarnations to enable a very wicked man to realise his true nature,
his Buddhahood.
Other attempts to develop Buddhist health care ethical
theories are generally both less complete and more conventional than
that of Keown. One approach has been to try to fit Buddhist and other
traditions' ideas about health care into four principles: autonomy,
beneficence/non-maleficence, justice, and autonomy (6). These four
principles have been very useful to many Western theorists, which is
not surprising as they are drawn from Western philosophical,
political, and medical sources. But do they apply well in the Buddhist
context (7)?
Dr. Pinit Ratanakul of Mahidol University in Thailand is one of the
leading Buddhist writers in the field of health care ethics. As would
be expected, he is Theravaadin, and his work is deeply rooted in his
Thai Buddhist tradition. He also has his doctorate in Philosophy from
Yale and this too has influenced his thinking.
In Dr. Ratanakul's 1986 book Bioethics: an Introduction to
the Ethics of Medicine and Life Sciences, he takes fidelity to the
medical profession, autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence and justice
as the "prima facie duties" that underlie bioethics (8). He does not
develop them from Buddhist texts, traditions, or arguments. Rather
they come from the Western philosophical and medical traditions.
Interestingly enough, in a later journal article,
"Bioethics in Thailand," Ratanakul turns to his Thai Theravaadin
tradition as the source for fundamental bioethical principles and
comes up with four. They are veracity, non-injury to life, justice,
and compassion (9). In the spirit of his comment, "There is much work
to be done both in clarifying these and other principles and in
applying them," (10) let us turn our attention to his 1986 and 1988
formulations with especial attention to how these principles cohere
with the teachings of the Lotus Suutra.
Autonomy
Dr. Ratanakul describes autonomy as the ability of an
individual "to order, plan, and choose among the diverse human
potentialities, the pattern of their own lives, as long as it is
consistent with meeting the rightful claims of others upon them and
the fulfilment of their responsibilities as moral agents" (11). In
traditional Buddhist ethics, autonomy is not featured as a major
category. The Buddhist emphasis on the responsibility of each person
for his or her own karma or moral character implies something like
this notion; however, there is something in the modern Western
insistence on autonomy that goes against the Buddhist grain. While Dr.
Ratanakul is careful not to fall into extremes, individualistic
autonomy is contrary to the central Buddhist insight of co-conditioned
causality, which insists on the interdependency of all beings. It is
particularly at odds with the bodhisattva ideal of sacrificing self
for others that is at the heart of the Lotus Suutra At any rate, we
note that in his later formulation, autonomy has dropped from Dr.
Ratanakul's list of fundamental principles.
Non-maleficence or ahimsa
Non-injury to living beings must, I think, be central to
any Buddhist medical ethical system. As Dr. Ratanakul put it, "In a
Buddhist society it is well known and accepted that a primary
obligation is non-injury to others" (12). Non-injury to life (ahimsa)
applies to all sentient life, but otherwise is the same as non-maleficence,
which in the Western world has usually referred only to human life,
although this may be slowly changing now. As mentioned earlier, Keown
also identifies ahimsa as a basic concept at the foundation of
Buddhist bioethics. Obviously, it is very powerful as a general
principle in health care ethics and, as noted above, pervades the
Lotus Suutra.
Justice
In his 1988 article Dr. Ratanakul identifies justice as a
basic Buddhist teaching and singles it out as one of the fundamental
principles on which to base a Buddhist bioethical system for Thailand.
He explains his concept of justice to be understood in terms of
impartiality and equal treatment, giving to each one what is his due.
People may be different from us either by their economic condition or
by their social status, but as moral potentialities they are equal to
us and therefore deserve equal treatment. (13)
This concept of justice is a modern Western one; compare
it to Gillon's formulation in Principles of Health Ethics where
justice is "often regarded as synonymous with fairness, and reasonably
summarised as the moral obligation to act on the basis of fair
adjudication between competing claims" (14). In practice, he
continues, justice is based on the principle of equality for all
persons and is discussed under three headings: "distributive justice"
or fairness in the allocation of resources, "rights-based justice" or
respect for individuals' rights, and "legal justice" or reliance on
fair legal codes and procedures.
Traditional Buddhist sources have very little to say about
justice. Buddhaghosa, for example, a Theravaadin scholar of the fourth
or fifth century CE, who may be the greatest exegete that Buddhism has
produced, does not seem to mention justice at all in his masterpiece,
the Visuddhimagga (15). Tachibana, in his still valuable 1926
path-breaking book The Ethics of Buddhism, attempts to formulate a
comprehensive ethical system from the texts of Theravaada Buddhism. In
the early parts of his book, he stays very close to the traditional
terminology and formulations, and does not mention justice at all.
Then he changes his tack and decides to reformulate Buddhist ethics
according to modern categories. "This is firstly to make the moral
ideas of the Buddha clearer, and secondly to see how far a moral
system designed twenty-four centuries ago can appeal to the modern
mind" (16).
Justice appears as a major category in his modern
reformulation, but he notes that it is not at all easy to find precise
equivalents from the Buddha's time to our own twentieth century for
such basic terms as justice, righteousness and impartiality (17). In
effect, he seems to admit that he was unable to show that justice is a
fundamental ancient Buddhist principle of social ethics. Nonetheless,
recognising that justice is a keystone for any ethical system which is
to appeal to people shaped by modern Western thought, he goes ahead in
a very appealing but not quite convincing way to use justice in his
scheme of Buddhist ethics.
A review of current work in the field of Buddhist ethics
generally confirms the impression that justice is not a fundamental
category of understanding in Buddhist thought. First, in the 1991 book
Buddhist Ethics and Modern Society, a compendium of papers from a
major international conference of Buddhist scholars, justice is only
mentioned in one passage, in the contribution of Sulak Sivaraksa, the
noted Buddhist reformer from Thailand (18). In his paper Sulak argues
that there is indirect support in Buddhist thought for a "minimum
distributive justice" (p. 163) from general Buddhist principles of the
middle way. Sulak notes that there is nothing in the scriptures or in
Theravaada tradition that directly advocates radical social
transformation.
Both Gunapala Dharmasiri's Fundamentals of Buddhist Ethics
(19), which appeared in 1989, and Damien Keown's The Nature of
Buddhist Ethics (20), a 1992 title, fail to discuss the issue of
justice as such although there are indirect discussions of related
issues. Two major books in the field appeared in 1995. The first,
Buddhism and Bioethics by Damien Keown, is interesting for its
complete lack of any discussion of justice (21). The term itself, I
believe, does not occur. Keown restricts his field of sources to the
Pali texts and thus does not draw upon historical or ethnographical
material. David Kalupahana, on the other hand, in his Ethics in Early
Buddhism, which mines the same sources as does Keown, devotes chapter
fifteen to "Law, Justice, and Morals" (22). There he argues that
dhamma (Sanskrit: dharma), which is one of the most fruitfully
pregnant terms in Buddhism, is the equivalent of "justice." At one
level this is true, but I think the equation is ultimately misleading,
since "justice" in the context of ancient India (the Pali and Sanskrit
context) is quite a different kettle of fish from justice in the
contemporary English-speaking world. Kalupahana also recognises this
implicitly, noting throughout the book that the Buddha's specific
teachings on social order focus on two quite different models.
First is the more or less democratic order of monks, and
second is lay society for which a universal king, following the
ancient Indian model, whose job it is to turn the wheel of Dharma for
the world, is offered as the ideal ruler. Neither of these forms, in
my opinion, has much to do with justice as understood in contemporary
Western countries such as Canada. These forms, however, have worked
well in the past in South and Southeast Asia as the foundations for a
good society, and are still live options. In East Asia, the
wheel-turning king as portrayed in the Lotus Suutra and other texts
has also been the model for the ideal ruler.
Kalupahana argues that both the polity of the monks and
the underlying basis for the universal wheel-turning monarch are
consistent with John Rawls' view of the foundations for achieving a
just society (23). I would agree with both Sulak and Kalupahana that
there is indirect support for ideas of social and individual justice
in Pali text Buddhist traditions. Or perhaps it would be better to say
that there is no contradiction between Buddhist traditional teachings
and the modern Western concepts of justice. Since Buddhism has been
very successful in adapting itself to all sorts of social realities,
and since we seem to be in an era where Western social forms are
increasingly dominant, perhaps it will be the work of Buddhists in the
twenty-first century to synthesise Buddhadharma and justice.
Such a synthesis may well be different from the current
egalitarianism in Western theories, if not practices, of justice. I
have not found much evidence for egalitarian justice as a major theme
in Buddhist tradition. Consider, for example, the way that Buddhaghosa
interpreted the precept against taking life:
"Taking life" is then the will to kill anything that one
perceives as having life…insofar as the will finds expression in
bodily action or in speech….In the case of humans the killing is the
more blameworthy the more virtuous they are. Apart from that the
extent of the offence is proportionate to the intensity of the wish to
kill. (24)The severity of the offence is a function of the amount of
virtue of the victim, hardly an egalitarian concept.
Dharmasiri notes that although the Buddha rejected the
caste system and taught that all persons are equal in that they are
subject to the same moral law and in that every person is a
potentially enlightened being (25), he also taught that class society
is inevitable. Classes do not have equal rights and duties; rather
they "should have reciprocal moral relationships with each other"
(26). Indeed, this seems to be the major principle behind social
relationships in traditional Buddhist countries and is quite
consistent with the teaching of the Lotus Suutra. The basic model is
paternalistic, as is very explicit in the case of the king, who, the
Buddha taught, should rule according to Dharma, "treating his subjects
as parents treat their own children" (27). Some of the parables of the
Lotus Suutra, such as the parable of the rich man and his sons in the
burning house (chapter three), the jewel in the gown (chapter eight),
and the skilled physician (chapter sixteen) spring to mind as powerful
teachings in favour of patriarchy.
These ancient, traditional social teachings do, however,
strongly support the provision of adequate health care for all people,
even all living creatures, in society. The higher individuals in the
reciprocal relationships have a duty to be concerned for the welfare
of those in their care, and this most definitely includes health
matters. For example, masters are taught to give their servants help
in times of sickness (28); and at the highest level, the king's first
duty to his subjects is to give them "help when and where it is
needed, i.e., a material or verbal or manual help" (29).
In Buddhist political thought, the Dharmaraja (the king
who rules by righteousness or by Buddhist principles) or cakravartin
(literally, the wheel-turner, or the king who turns the wheel of
righteousness) is the ideal ruler (30). The royal precepts and virtues
enumerated above are drawn from that tradition. Asoka, an emperor in
India who reigned in the third century BCE, is the king revered today
as the one who most nearly embodied the Dharmaraja ideal, and he was
very vigorous in promoting non-harming as a principle of governance
and as a way of life for his subjects. As well, he took great interest
in the physical welfare of his subjects and provided medical herbs to
be distributed free of charge to the people of his kingdom and also to
the animals (31).
It seems that justice in the egalitarian sense does not
have a firm base in Buddhist traditional thought. Perhaps a sounder
Buddhist case for an equitable distribution of health services could
be built on the foundations of karuna (compassion), a fundamental
virtue for all Buddhists, friendship as a "basic good" (borrowing from
Keown), and on the noblesse oblige expected of the ideal Buddhist
monarch, all of which seem to be consistent with the teachings of the
Lotus Suutra. All three of these entail helping the poor: karuna and
friendship as primary virtues should motivate individuals, whether
commoners or royal, and the state should manifest the ideals of the
Dharmaraja, the king who rules according to the teachings of the
Buddha (32).
Compassion and beneficence
Compassion is one of the most fundamental Buddhist
categories, so fundamental that the entirety of the tradition can be
described as compassion (karuna) and wisdom (prajna) working together.
It is important to keep in mind that the two are linked and one
without the other is dangerous. For example, a person who is not wise
may cause enormous problems by witlessly attempting to be
compassionate, and a person who has penetrating insight without
compassion is very dangerous indeed.
In order to help one attain this balance, to make sure
that the practitioner develops skilful means (upaaya), certain sublime
states of mind are cultivated in Buddhism. There are four of these
taught by all schools of Buddhists and recognised as necessary for
living a moral life, generating kusala karma, or skilful deeds, rather
than the opposite. The four are loving kindness for all sentient
beings, compassion for the unhappiness of others, sympathetic joy for
the happiness and good fortune of others, and equanimity (33). On the
level of practice, the Lotus Suutra could be interpreted as no less
than an extended sermon on how to live the transcendental bodhisattva
path by using skilful means compassionately, thus embodying the four
sublime states just detailed. Were a nation to be governed according
to these impulses, its health care system would be a most excellent
manifestation of Buddhist beneficence.
Veracity
The fourth principle which Dr. Ratanakul sees as essential
in Buddhist biomedical ethics is veracity, which he firmly bases on
another of the five basic moral precepts: "I undertake to observe the
rule to abstain from false speech." In applying this precept to
medical ethics, he concludes that one must always tell the complete
truth to the patient. Failure to disclose the truth is generally, he
argues, due to denial and fear on part of medical personnel. If the
patient does not know all the facts of his or her condition, then his
or her "strength, will-power, and endurance" (34) will be compromised.
Buddhists know that life is hard and full of suffering and have always
taught that these truths must be dealt with frankly and openly. Hiding
from the unpleasant side of things is not part of the Buddhist way.
This insistence on veracity fits in very well with the
current doctrine in Western medicine that the patient as an autonomous
moral agent has a responsibility for his or her own health and care.
However, in the Mahaayaana tradition, there is rather different
approach to the issue of veracity. In chapter sixteen of the Lotus
Suutra, there is a parable where the Buddha compares himself to a
skilful physician. All his sons have foolishly taken some powerful,
poisonous medicine. Those who are most deranged by the poison refuse
to take the antidote which he has quickly prepared. Therefore, he
deceives them by feigning his own death, thereby shocking them back
into their right minds so that they will take the remedy. Lord Buddha
rhetorically asks the assembly, "Is there any man who can say that
this good physician is guilty of the sin of wilfully false speech, or
is there not?" And they reply: "There is not, O World-Honored One"
(35). In his discussion of the Lotus Suutra in his recent book of
readings, Buddhism in Practice, Donald Lopez demurs from the judgement
of the assembly. He argues that "the claim to legitimacy of the
earlier tradition is usurped by the Mahaayaana through the explanation
that what the Buddha had taught before was in fact a lie" (36), albeit
a compassionately motivated lie. Too strong by far (37), but it does
point to an interesting question: is it not possible for the doctrine
of skilful means, in less than skilful hands, to lead in a direction
away from the Dharma? The parables of the Lotus Suutra are taught as
examples of upaaya or skilful means. It would seem that deception on
the level of relative truth is quite justified as long as it advances
the cause of absolute truth and, as in the story of the skilful
physician, is beneficent. Of course, if a deception led to harm of
sentient beings, it would be unskilful rather than skilful. Thus, in
Mahaayaana thought at least, a case could be made for the health care
team withholding the truth or even deceiving a patient if such
withholding or deception was thought for good reason to be
therapeutic.
This sort of paternalism is no longer stylish in the West
and many current health care ethicists reject it, including Dr.
Ratanakul, who writes, "The practice of paternalism in regard to
truth-telling is therefore unacceptable to Buddhism" (38). Although
his argument for veracity on medical, general ethical, and Buddhist
grounds is strong, it nonetheless seems to me that his conclusion is
overstated, especially in regard to the Mahaayaana. Medical
paternalism may be justifiable in traditional Buddhist societies,
which accept that society is to be governed by ancient hierarchical
principles enshrined in the texts and traditions of Buddhism. It
certainly is the current practice in Japan in regard to cancer
diagnosis, where physicians practically never reveal the truth to
their patients. While Mahaayaana teachings on skilful means provide a
theoretical justification for this, Japanese cultural attitudes
towards bodily disintegration are also important (39).
References to medicine in the Lotus Suutra
(1) Parable of the skilful physician.
This parable, which occurs in chapter sixteen, is perhaps
the most relevant and important passage in the Lotus Suutra in regard
to the practice of medicine.It has been discussed above.
(2) Parable of the medicinal herbs.
Chapter five consists of a lovely parable about how
beneficent waters nourish all plants without discrimination, whether
they are tiny medicinal herbs or awe-inspiring giant trees. In the
Chinese version of the text, the one which is influential in the Far
Eastern Buddhist communities, there does not seem to be anything in
this chapter that applies to medicine or medical ethics. The Sanskrit
version (translated by Hurwitz and Kern) ends with a lengthy parable
that is interesting in this regard. In this parable a man who has been
blind from birth relies on his own experience to deny that there are
any shapes at all in the world to be seen. A compassionate and
supremely skilful physician takes pity on this man and collects and
prepares four wondrous herbs which restore the man's sight. Seeing
heavenly bodies for the first time, he now claims to be all-seeing and
to have attained perfect extinction. Wise seers quickly correct him
and point out how ignorant he actually remains.
This parable makes use of the classical metaphor of the
Buddha as the supremely skilled physician. It could be taken as a
practical example for all Buddhists, who should emulate his compassion
by applying their efforts and skills to treating the ill. It is also
making one of the primary points of the Lotus Suutra, that those who
follow the lesser of the three vehicles need to be reminded that they
are a long way indeed from the ultimate goal.
(3) Bodhisattva-mahasattva Medicine King.
The bodhisattva Medicine King (Bhaisajya-raja) occurs in
several places in the Lotus Suutra. These passages seem to foreshadow
the celestial Medicine Buddha (Bhaisajya-guru), who became very
important in the Buddhist traditions of the Far East (40). The
Medicine Buddha is very explicitly charged with taking care of the
physical and mental health of devotees and has taken vows to that
effect. In the Lotus Suutra the medical aspects of the bodhisattva
Medicine King are not obvious.
Chapter ten on the Teacher of the Law begins with the Lord
Buddha addressing the assembly through the bodhisattva Medicine King,
but I find no medical references at all in the chapter. Similarly
chapter thirteen on Holding Firm begins by mentioning bodhisattva
Medicine King as part of the audience, but has nothing in it about
medicine. Some of the Buddha's previous existences are covered in
chapter twenty-three, a very interesting chapter in which the
bodhisattva offers his entire body, his arms, and his fingers out of
reverence as fire offerings, a practice which was frequently emulated
up until recent times (41). Near the end of chapter twenty-three there
is a reference to the medical efficacy of the Lotus Suutra: anyone who
hears it will be cured of sickness, old age, and death.
In the Dharani chapter, chapter twenty-six, the
bodhisattva Medicine King offers a dharani for the protection of those
who preach the Lotus Suutra. The spell has no medical references.
However, in the same chapter, a horde of female demons offer a dharani
that protects men, women, boys, and girls against all manners of
demonic beings and against all manners of fevers. The final mention in
passing of the bodhisattva Medicine King, along with his brother
Medicine Superior, is in chapter twenty-seven dedicated to these two
bodhisattvas' father. There are no medical references.
In summary, it appears that the passages about the
bodhisattva Medicine King, rather surprisingly, tell us little about
the practice of medicine or of medical ethics.
(4) Medical benefits to those who revere the Lotus Sutra
and medical penalties to those who do not respect it.
Both chapter fourteen on bodhisattva practices and chapter
eighteen on the benefits of joyous response to the Lotus Suutra detail
the health benefits which accrue to those who have joy and faith in
the Suutra itself. As noted earlier, chapter twenty-three mentions
similar wonderful effects.
On the other hand, those who slander or disparage the
Lotus Suutra have much to lose. In chapter three there is a passage
that says that anyone who speaks badly of the teachings shall be
afflicted with all sorts of congenital deformities and illnesses.
Furthermore, he or she will be unable to heal anyone else, and any
medical attention he or she receives will exacerbate the condition
treated. At the very end of the Lotus Suutra—perhaps the placement of
this passage is a sign of its importance—terrible medical results are
promised for those who disparage believers of the Suutra. Blindness,
deformity, or leprosy will be their fate for generation after
generation.(5) Bodhisattva practices
Chapter fourteen details appropriate activities for one
who is cultivating the bodhisattva path, and chapter twenty-five is a
marvellous account of how a bodhisattva of great attainment, namely
Avalokitesvara, is able to help anyone who calls on him in a time of
need. I find it interesting and somewhat surprising that medical
matters are completely absent from both sets of practices. However, in
the introductory chapter, bodhisattvas are commended for offering
hundreds of different kinds of medicines to the Buddha and his monks.
(6) Inquiries about the health of the Lord Buddha
The appearance of the jewelled stupa in the sky in chapter eleven and
the emergence from the earth of an astounding number of bodhisattvas
in chapter fifteen are examples of the very exalted nature of buddhas
in the Mahaayaana. It is a little jolting to find similar simple
inquiries about the health and vigour of the World-Honoured One:
Is the World-Honoured One at ease,
With few ailments and few troubles?
In instructing the all the living beings,
Is he free from weariness? (42)
It is very strange to me that one so inconceivably
splendid could possibly be ill or weary, and thus these well-meaning
inquiries seem out of place.
Conclusion
In the study of ethics in the West there is widespread
agreement, perhaps an emerging consensus, that certain
principles—autonomy, beneficence, non-malfeasance, and justice—apply
prima facie to health care issues. Not all of these four principles
fit into a Buddhist framework. Two of them, however, do fit well.
Non-malfeasance and the Buddhist principle of ahimsa (non-harming)
appear to be practically identical. Furthermore, karuna (compassion),
which perhaps is the central ethical principle of the Buddhist
tradition, is very similar indeed to beneficence. Autonomy is also
important in Buddhist practice, but, as argued above, is not central,
and there are important differences both in theory and in application
to health care from the way it is understood in the West.Justice seems
to be the sticking point. Egalitarian justice is not part of
traditional Buddhism, although justice in health care can be
approached using other Buddhist ideas and practices. As noted in the
introduction, Buddhism has a wonderful flexibility, enabling it to
adapt to and to learn from new situations. It is noteworthy, I think,
that converts to Buddhism in the Western world, eastern Buddhists who
have settled in the West, and those like Dr. Ratanakul who have been
influenced by Western thought, are tending to make justice a central
Buddhist value (43).
"Cease to do evil, learn to do good, cleanse your own
heart," the catch phrase which is popularly used to sum up the essence
of Buddhism, suggests how important non-malfeasance, beneficence, and
self-reliance or moral autonomy are in Buddhist thought. All three are
aspects of karuna (compassion) and upaaya (skilful means), the
qualities necessary to function well in the world as a Buddhist. These
relative qualities must, of course, work in conjunction with prajna
(wisdom), insight into absolute truth. To be true to the Buddhist
tradition, any theoretical system of health care ethics must be based
on wisdom and compassion, and all applications should manifest skilful
means. The underlying principles of the Lotus Suutra are consistent
with these, and the parables and references to medical matters offer
some specific guidance. At the present, with the tremendous changes
and challenges taking place in the heath care field, Buddhist thought,
by applying wisdom, compassion, and skilful means to both theory and
practice, can make a tremendous contribution to bioethics.
Editions of the Lotus Suutra consulted
Bunno, H., W. E. Soothill, et al., trans. The Threefold
Lotus Sutra. Tokyo, New York: Kosei, Weatherhill, 1975.
Hurvitz, Leon, trans. Scripture of the Lotus Blossom of
the Fine Dharma. New York: Colombia University Press, 1976.
Kern, H., trans. SadDharma–Pundarika, or the Lotus of the
True Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1884.Watson, Burton, trans. The
Lotus Sutra. New York: Columbia University Press, 1993.
Notes:
1- Raoul Birnbaum, The Healing Buddha (Boulder: Shambhala,
1979).
2- The Journal of Buddhist Ethics, vol. 3 (1996), has six
papers from the 1995 American Academy of Religion panel "Revisioning
Buddhist Ethics." These papers reflect some of the current excitement
and flux in the general field of Buddhist ethics. Their general
comments are very apt as well for Buddhist health care ethics. One of
their recurring themes is to suggest that there is very little
commonality in theoretical approaches to ethical reasoning in Buddhist
texts and traditions. It seems to me that there are many authentic
ways or tools that Buddhists have used throughout the centuries to
think about ethical issues, just as there are many paths in Christian
and Western ethics. Today, modern Buddhists, both Eastern and Western,
are coming to grips with new problems and issues and are struggling to
come up with practical solutions that are true to their religious
heritage and their national traditions. No unified answers or
approaches can be expected, and such really are not to be hoped for in
the Buddhist tradition which respects diversity.
3- Damien Keown, Buddhism and Bioethics (New York: St.
Martin's Press, 1995).
4- Ibid., pp. 43ff.
5- Ibid., pp. 51ff.
6- Raanan Gillon, ed., Principles of Health Care Ethics (Chichester:
Wiley, 1994). This very large book attempts to apply the four
principles across the board around the world with varying success. For
a good discussion of the four principles see the editor's introductory
essay, "Medical Ethics and the Four Principles."
7- What follows in the remainder of this section is based
upon my paper "Buddhism and the Four Principles" in Gillon,
Principles, pp. 105–116.
8- P. Ratanakul, Bioethics: an Introduction to the Ethics
of Medicine and Life Sciences (Bangkok : Mahidol University, 1986), p.
86.
9- P. Ratanakul, "Bioethics in Thailand: the Struggle for
Buddhist Solutions," The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy (1988),
pp. 13:301–312.
10- Ibid., p. 312.
11- Ratanakul, "Bioethics: an Introduction," pp. 83–84.
12- Ibid., p. 54.
13- Ratanakul, "Bioethics in Thailand," p. 311.
14- Gillon, "Medical Ethics," Principles, p. xxv.
15- Buddhaghosa, The Path of Purification (Visuddhimagga),
2 vols. (Berkeley and London, 1976), Lamotte, Histoire du Buddhisme
Indien, vol. 1, (Louvain: Université du Louvain, 1976), pp. 25ff., and
several other basic source books yielded nothing on justice as an
early Buddhist concern. Similarly, S. Punyanubhab, "An Outline of
Buddhist Tenets," in National Identity Board's Buddhism in Thai Life
(Bangkok: Funny Publishing Limited Partnership, 1981), pp. 19–28, and
other contemporary popular treatments of Buddhism fail to include
justice as a fundamental tenet.
16- S. Tachibana, The Ethics of Buddhism (1926; reprint,
London: Curzon, 1975), p. 95.
17- Ibid., pp. 264–265; see A. L. Basham, The Wonder that
was India (New York : Grove Press, 1959), pp. 114–117 and passim, for
an indication of how very different the ancient Indian concept of
justice is from the current Western notion.
18- Sulak Sivaraksa, "Buddhist Ethics and Modern Politics:
A Theravada Viewpoint," Buddhist Ethics and Modern Society: An
International Symposium, ed. Charles Wei-hsun Fu and Sandra A.
Wawrytko (New York: Greenwood Press, 1991), pp. 163–64.
19- Gunapala Dharmasiri, Fundamentals of Buddhist Ethics
(Antioch, California: Golden Leave, 1989).
20- Damien Keown, The Nature of Buddhist Ethics (New York:
St. Martin's Press, 1992).
21- Damien Keown, Buddhism and Bioethics.
22- David J. Kalupahana, Ethics in Early Buddhism
(Honolulu: University of Hawai'i Press, 1995).
23- Kalupahana, Ethics, p. 125.
24- E. Conze, trans. Buddhist Scriptures (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1959), pp. 70–71.
25- Dharmasiri, Fundamentals, p. 62.
26- Ibid., p. 61.
27- S. B. Indr, "The King in Buddhist Tradition," Buddhism
in Thai Life, p. 61.
28- Phra Dhammadhajamuni, Outline of Buddhism, 2nd. ed.
(Bangkok: Mahamakut Buddhist University, B.E. 2530). p. 43.
29- Ibid., p. 53.
30- S. J. Tambiah, World Conqueror and World Renouncer: a
Study of Buddhism and Polity in Thailand against a Historical
Background (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976).
31- Basham, Wonder, pp. 53–57, 500.
32- It seems to me from my time in Thailand that the royal
family there lives up to these Buddhist ideals very well indeed by
sponsoring and financing many public health and other health-related
projects. See, for example, T. Kraivixien, His Majesty King Bhumibol
Adulyadej: Compassionate Monarch of Thailand (Bangkok: Kathavethin
Foundation, 1982).
33- S. Taniguchi, A Study of Biomedical Ethics from a
Buddhist Perspective (Berkeley: Graduate Theological Union and
Institute of Buddhist Studies), pp. 65–69 and E. Conze, Buddhist
Meditation (London: Unwin, 1972), pp. 118–132. Dr. Steven K.H. Aung in
his "Loving Kindness: The Essential Buddhist Contribution to Primary
Care," Humane Health Care International [formerly Humana], vol. 12.2
(April, 1996), pp. 81–84, does an excellent job of explaining how
metta can function in the day to day practice of medicine.
34- Ratanakul, "Bioethics in Thailand," p. 308.
35- L. Hurvitz, trans., Scripture of the Lotus Blossom of
the Fine Dharma (New York: Columbia University Press, 1976), p. 240.
36- Donald S. Lopez, Buddhism in Practice (Princeton, New
Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1995), p. 29.
37- Nikayo Niwano, A Guide to the Threefold Lotus Sutra
(Tokyo: Kosei, 1981), pp. 110ff., provides a good corrective to
Lopez's position.
38- P. Ratanakul, "Bioethics in Thailand," p. 308.
39- E. Ohnuki-Tierney, Illness and Culture in Contemporary
Japan: An Anthropological View (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1984), pp. 62–65, 207–208.
40- Birnbaum, Healing Buddha, and Nakamura Hajime,
"Buddhism, Schools of: Mahayana Buddhism," The Encyclopedia of
Religion, vol. 2, Mircea Eliade, ed. (New York: Macmillan, 1967), p.
459.
41- Lopez, Practice, chapter 36; Paul Williams, Mahayana
Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations. (London and New York: Routledge,
1989), pp. 154–155. In the introductory chapter to the Lotus Suutra it
is noted with approval that bodhisattvas give their own flesh, hands,
and feet as offerings.
42- Bunno Kato, W.E. Soothill, et al., trans., The
Threefold Lotus Sutra (Tokyo, New York: Kosei, Weatherhill, 1975), p.
239.
43- F. Eppsteiner and D. Maloney, eds. The Path of
Compassion: Contemporary Writings on Engaged Buddhism (Berkeley,
California and Buffalo, New York: Buddhist Peace Fellowship and White
Pine Press, 1985). This book is a good introduction to this
phenomenon.
Source : www.buddhismtoday.com
Update : 01-12-2001
--o0o--
|